共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
2.
3.
The purpose of this paper is not to define civil disobedience, but to identify a paradigm case of civil disobedience and the features exemplified in it. After noting the benefits of this methodological approach, the paper proceeds with an examination of two key, interconnected features: conscientiousness and communication. First, a link is made between the conscientious aspect of civil disobedience and moral consistency; a civil disobedient demonstrates a conscientious commitment to certain values through her willingness to condemn, and to dissociate herself from, governmental decisions that violate those values. A parallel is then drawn between the communicative aspect of civil disobedience and the communicative aspect of lawful punishment by the state. Both practices are associated with an aim to demonstrate protest against certain types of conduct and an aim to bring about a change in that conduct. In paradigm situations, a civil disobedient aims to lead policymakers not only to reform existing law, but also to internalise her objections so as to produce a lasting change in the law. Having such aims places some constraints upon the modes of communication that she reasonably may use to achieve these aims. This paper concludes by considering three controversial modes of communication -- coercion, publicity and violence.I wish to thank Adam Cureton, John Gardner, David Garrard, Kinch Hoekstra, Peter Jones, Christoph Ortner and John Tasioulas for their helpful comments on previous drafts of this paper.
For one definition of civil disobedience, see John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1971), 364. See also Hugo A. Bedau, On Civil Disobedience, Journal of Philosophy, 58/21 (1961), 653--61. For an alternative definition, see Joseph Raz, The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), 263. 相似文献
4.
Alan Carter 《Journal of applied philosophy》1998,15(1):29-47
The article defends the forms of civil disobedience currently practised by environmental protesters. It reviews the justifications of civil disobedience by Dworkin, Rawls and Singer, and finds them more or less wanting. A new and more extensive justification is provided on the basis of our duties to prevent harm befalling future generations. 相似文献
5.
6.
7.
8.
Just as Beautiful but not (Necessarily) a Supertask 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
9.
Howe ML 《Psychological science》2005,16(12):927-931
The role of inhibition in children's (5-, 7-, and 11-year-olds') false memory illusions in the Deese-Roediger-McDermott (DRM) paradigm was examined using a list-wise directed-forgetting procedure. Children studied either a single DRM list (control) or two DRM lists in succession with a directed-remembering instruction or a directed-forgetting instruction between list presentations. The findings indicated that, like adults, children effectively suppressed the output of true memories when given a directed-forgetting instruction. Unlike adults, whose false memories are not attenuated in directed-forgetting conditions, children suppressed false memories at recall in the directed-forgetting condition. Because recognition data indicated that the children did generate false memories regardless of instruction, it appears that although adults' false memories are generated automatically and do not become part of their conscious experience, children's false memories are produced with greater effort and conscious processing, and as a result are easier to suppress at output. 相似文献
10.
Eric Mack 《Ethical Theory and Moral Practice》1999,2(2):87-115
This paper offers a programmatic philosophical articulation of moral and political individualism. This individualism consists of two main components: value individualism and rights individualism. The former is the view that, for each individual, the end which is of ultimate value is his own well-being. Each individual's well-being has ultimate agent-relative value and the only ultimate values are these agent-relative values. The latter view is that individuals possess moral jurisdiction over themselves, i.e., rights of self-ownership. These rights (along with other rights individuals may come to possess) constrain the manner in which agents may pursue value. For this reason, the articulated individualism is an constrained individualism. Sketches of arguments are offered for both value and rights individualism. And it is argued that the sole legitimate function of legal/political institutions is to further delineate and protect the rights of individuals. However, the paper is also concerned to indicate why this radical moral and political individualism does not have many of the features or implications that are commonly ascribed to it. In this connection, I seek to show how this social doctrine accords with individuals' having concern for the well-being of others, with the emergence of relationships among individuals that have both instrumental and non-instrumental value, with a degree of responsibility for self and others that is often thought to be antithetical to individualism and, in general, with a flourishing of civil order. 相似文献
11.
12.
13.
Loewy EH 《Theoretical medicine and bioethics》2005,26(6):445-468
This paper argues that we have wrongly and not for the patient’s benefit made a form of stark autonomy our highest value which
allows physicians to slip out from under their basic duty which has always been to pursue a particular patient’s good. In
general – I shall argue – it is the patient’s right to select his or her own goals and the physician’s duty to inform the
patient of the feasibility of that goal and of the means needed to attain it. If the goal is not one that is possible, the
patient, with the physician and family, must select a feasible goal and then discuss the costs/benefits of various approaches.
The physician should take a leading role in helping the patient select the goal. I argue that to simply present a laundry
list of means and insist that patients choose for themselves is not only abandoning patients to their autonomy but is, in
fact, a crass form of violating the patient’s autonomy. Freely choosing not to choose is a choice a patient with decisional
capacity is entitled to make and one that needs to be respected. 相似文献
14.
15.
16.
17.
The sensitivity condition on knowledge says that one knows that P only if one would not believe that P if P were false. Difficulties
for this condition are now well documented. Keith DeRose has recently suggested a revised sensitivity condition that is designed
to avoid some of these difficulties. We argue, however, that there are decisive objections to DeRose’s revised condition.
Yet rather than simply abandoning his proposed condition, we uncover a rationale for its adoption, a rationale which suggests
a further revision that avoids our objections as well as others. The payoff is considerable: along the way to our revision,
we learn lessons about the epistemic significance of certain explanatory relations, about how we ought to envisage epistemic
closure principles, and about the epistemic significance of methods of belief formation. 相似文献
18.
Matthew R. Sutherland 《Cognition & emotion》2018,32(3):616-622
Previous findings indicate that negative arousal enhances bottom-up attention biases favouring perceptual salient stimuli over less salient stimuli. The current study tests whether those effects were driven by emotional arousal or by negative valence by comparing how well participants could identify visually presented letters after hearing either a negative arousing, positive arousing or neutral sound. On each trial, some letters were presented in a high contrast font and some in a low contrast font, creating a set of targets that differed in perceptual salience. Sounds rated as more emotionally arousing led to more identification of highly salient letters but not of less salient letters, whereas sounds’ valence ratings did not impact salience biases. Thus, arousal, rather than valence, is a key factor enhancing visual processing of perceptually salient targets. 相似文献
19.
Andrew Jason Cohen 《The Philosophical forum》1999,30(4):269-288
20.
Peter B. M. Vranas 《Journal of Philosophical Logic》2010,39(1):59-71
“Surrender; therefore, surrender or fight” is apparently an argument corresponding to an inference from an imperative to an
imperative. Several philosophers, however (Williams 1963; Wedeking 1970; Harrison 1991; Hansen 2008), have denied that imperative
inferences exist, arguing that (1) no such inferences occur in everyday life, (2) imperatives cannot be premises or conclusions
of inferences because it makes no sense to say, for example, “since surrender” or “it follows that surrender or fight”, and
(3) distinct imperatives have conflicting permissive presuppositions (“surrender or fight” permits you to fight without surrendering,
but “surrender” does not), so issuing distinct imperatives amounts to changing one’s mind and thus cannot be construed as
making an inference. In response I argue inter alia that, on a reasonable understanding of ‘inference’, some everyday-life
inferences do have imperatives as premises and conclusions, and that issuing imperatives with conflicting permissive presuppositions
does not amount to changing one’s mind. 相似文献