共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
Rodolfo Garau 《British Journal for the History of Philosophy》2016,24(2):231-256
This paper focuses on an understudied aspect of Hobbes's natural philosophy: his approach to the domain of life. I concentrate on the role assigned by Hobbes to the heart, which occupies a central role in both his account of human physiology (which he names ‘vital motion’) and of the origin of animal locomotion (‘animal or voluntary motion’). With this, I have three goals in mind. First, I aim to offer a cross-section of Hobbes's effort to provide a mechanistic picture of human life. Second, I aim to contextualize Hobbes's views in the seventeenth-century debates on human physiology and animal locomotion. In particular, I will compare Hobbes's views with the theories put forth by Harvey, Descartes, the Galenic, and Peripatetic traditions. Also, I will show that Hobbes was receptive to advances within contemporary English physiology and chemistry. Third, by means of a comparison with Descartes, I advance some hypothesis to explain why Hobbes indentified the heart, and not the brain (as was increasingly common in his day), as the organ originating animal locomotion. In this regard, I trace out some possible implications of Hobbes's views on human physiology and locomotion for his psychology and political philosophy. 相似文献
2.
Weimin Mo 《Frontiers of Philosophy in China》2007,2(2):247-264
Cogito, as the first principle of Descartes’ metaphysical system, initiated the modern philosophy of consciousness, becoming both the source and subject of modern Western philosophical discourse. The philosophies of Maine de Biran, Kant, Husserl, Heidegger, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, and others developed by answering the following questions? Is consciousness substantial or not? Does consciousness require the guarantee of a transcendental subject? Is Cogito epistemological or ontological? Am I a being-for-myself or a being-for-others? Outlining the developmental history of the idea of Cogito from Descartes to Sartre is important for totally comprehending the evolution and development of Western philosophy. 相似文献
3.
Mark Glouberman 《British Journal for the History of Philosophy》2013,21(5):873-886
In Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry, Bernard Williams supplies an interpretation of Descartes's Meditations in which the meditator's clean sweep of initial beliefs is justified by a stance that abrogates all practical pressures: the stance of pure enquiry. Otherwise, Williams explains, it would not be reasonable to set many of the initial beliefs aside. Nowhere, however, does Descartes assert that his approach is in this sense ‘pure’. It would of course be preferable if the meditator's rejection of all the initial beliefs did not require an abrogation of the conditions that govern everyday belief-formation and assessment. I supply a reading that accomplishes this. The key to this reading is recognition that Descartes is a thinker of his time, a time when the pre-modern worldview was being systematically rejected. I show, in this regard, that when Descartes characterizes a belief as ‘uncertain’, this has the implication that the belief is false. And, certainly, the rational policy, without need for any special stance, is to reject falsehoods. 相似文献
4.
5.
6.
Thomas V. Frederick 《Pastoral Psychology》2008,56(4):413-419
The core cosmological dimension of Solution-Focused Brief Therapy (SFBT) and Christianity emphasizes a similar truth—the future
is now. As humans live in their preferred realities, they experience the future, problem free solution for their lives from
a SFBT perspective. The Christian tradition emphasizes the in-breaking Kingdom of God beginning with the Christ event. The
end has entered the now. However, the final consummation of the end-times is still as yet in the future which means that sin
and death are part of the world. This Christian understanding of sin and fallenness provides humility to SFBT’s inherently
positive view of the world (Bidwell, D. R. Am J of Pastor Couns, 3:3–21, 1999), while SFBT encourages Christians to see the
kingdom of God in the now instead of the future. 相似文献
7.
《Theology & Sexuality》2013,19(2):145-157
AbstractThe article investigates how God is represented in popular culture, especially in music, in Brazil. It gives a general background about Brazilian culture showing how religion is part of the identity constructions of Brazilian people and how it is marked by multiplicity, syncretism and hybridization. It then analyses two popular songs that make explicit statements about "who God is" and how those statements are related to traditional masculine gender constructions. Finally, the article discusses how issues of masculinity and religion have been approached in recent scholarship and points to the need for other ways of imagining God that are related to people's experience. 相似文献
8.
Meifen Wei Tsun‐Yao Ku Hwei‐Jane Chen Nathaniel Wade Kelly Yu‐Hsin Liao Gwo‐Jen Guo 《Counseling and values》2012,57(2):162-180
This study examined whether attachment to God moderated the relation between perceived stress and well‐being (i.e., life satisfaction and positive affect) among 183 Chinese Christian international students and immigrants. Results showed significant main effects of (a) perceived stress on life satisfaction and (b) secure attachment to God and avoidant attachment to God on life satisfaction and positive affect. There was a significant interaction of perceived stress and avoidant attachment to God on life satisfaction. Specifically, high avoidant attachment to God exacerbated the association between perceived stress and life satisfaction, whereas low avoidant attachment to God buffered the association between perceived stress and life satisfaction. 相似文献
9.
Anselm K. Min 《International Journal for Philosophy of Religion》2006,60(1-3):99-116
In this essay I present the postmodern phenomenological approach of Levinas, Derrida, and Marion to the problem of naming
the unnameable God. For Levinas, God is never experienced directly but only as a third person whose infinity is testified
to in the infinity of responsibility to the hungry. For Derrida, God remains the unnameable “wholly other” accessible only
as the indeterminate term of pure reference in prayer. For Marion, God remains the object of “de-nomination” through praise.
In all three, the problem of naming the unnameable God is necessarily linked to how we relate to fellow human beings, to the
hungry in Levinas, justice in Derrida, and charity in Marion. I also reflect on the merits and adequacy of phenomenology as
such for speaking of divine transcendence. 相似文献
10.
Robert Oakes 《International Journal for Philosophy of Religion》2008,64(3):155-160
Many philosophers have contended that (traditional) theism or supernaturalism suffers from what can properly be called the
Problem of Divine Hiddenness (the PDH). [See Howard-Snyder and Moser 2002]. Moreover, it is the contention of many proponents of the PDH that this “problem,” if, indeed, not just a component of the “problem of evil,” bears a striking similarity to the latter. Specifically, at the heart of this ostensible difficulty for theism is that Divine “Hiddenness,” like pain
and suffering—or at least pain and suffering in the amount that the world contains—is precisely the opposite of what one would
expect if there existed a (maximally great) supernatural Person. Accordingly, it is maintained by proponents of the PDH that supernaturalism is disconfirmed by the relevant “problem.” The aim of this essay is to establish that there is more than ample metaphysical warrant (of a
sort overlooked thus far) for maintaining that the “hiddenness” of God is exactly what should be expected if theism is true. Thus, the conclusion we hope to secure is that the PDH has considerably less to recommend it than its proponents have thought, and, accordingly, that it fails to constitute an
effective threat to supernaturalism. 相似文献
11.
Piotr Rajski 《Journal of religion and health》2003,42(3):181-190
In this paper the author shares some of his experiences of using silence in therapy. He presents one of the modes of practicing silence, namely the meditation technique known as Contemplative Prayer, and shows advantages of using this technique in the process of self-purification and self-balancing of the therapist. The author stipulates that silence is a royal way to discovering God. Finding this divine particle within oneself and client changes the whole outlook of therapy. The therapist is no longer alone with the client, but God becomes an active participant in the therapeutic process through His love for both therapist and client. 相似文献
12.
In this article I concentrate on three issues. First, Graham Oppy’s treatment of the relationship between the concept of infinity
and Zeno’s paradoxes lay bare several porblems that must be dealt with if the concept of infinity is to do any intellectual
work in philosophy of religion. Here I will expand on some insightful remarks by Oppy in an effort ot adequately respond to
these problems. Second, I will do the same regarding Oppy’s treatment of Kant’s first antinomy in the first critique, which
deals in part with the question of whether the world had a beginning in time or if time extends infinitely into the past.
And third, my examination of these two issues will inform what I have to say regarding a key topic in philosophy of religion:
the question regarding the proper relationship between the infinite and the finite in the concept of God. 相似文献
13.
14.
15.
Paolo Diego Bubbio 《International Journal of Philosophical Studies》2013,21(5):689-706
AbstractThis paper covers the theme of the death of God considered from a Hegelian standpoint. For Aristotle, the image of God as ‘thought thinking itself’ was an image of the knowledge aspired to in philosophy. With the notion of God becoming man and his insistence on the icon of the Cross, Hegel challenged the Aristotelian goal of philosophy as immutable knowledge of an ‘ultimate’ reality. Hegel viewed the crisis of normativity (the death of the Cartesian divine guarantor) as strictly linked to the conception of the self. It is Nietzsche who is best known for alluding to the full significance of this image for modern life, but Hegel’s thought on the complex relations of philosophy and religion in the modern world can be regarded as an attempt to think through this same historical phenomenon. In this paper, I focus on the philosophical relevance of Hegel’s notion of the death of God. I argue that unpacking the significance of the ‘truths’ presented symbolically in modern Christianity is crucial in understanding the requirements that an idealistic philosophy must meet. 相似文献
16.
Abstract: Recent developments in the neurosciences have made possible the advent of brain‐machine interfaces, potentially altering our understanding of our relationship with technology and even the very meaning of what it is to be human. This article briefly examines some of the recent developments in neuroengineering and considers the ethical implications. Working from Jesus' miracles as well as from a dynamic understanding of the image of God, I argue that the categories of healing and transformation should be employed in thinking through the implications of brain‐machine interfaces specifically and neuroengineering generally. Although the vocabulary of the cyborg may represent the newfound freedom that this technology can bring, the category of the face may serve as a reminder of the boundedness of human nature. 相似文献
17.
Peter Scott 《Zygon》2000,35(2):371-384
This paper begins from the premise that being in the image of God refers humanity neither to nature nor to its technology but to God. Two positions are thereby rejected: (1) that nature should be treated as a source of salvation (Heidegger), and (2) that redemptive significance may be ascribed to technology (Cole-Turner, Hefner). Instead, theological judgments concerning technologyrequire the reconstruction of theological anthropology. To this end, the image of God ( imago dei ) is reconceived in terms of sociality , temporality , and spatiality to show how humanity may be understood as imaging God in a technological society. 相似文献
18.
Mark Wynn 《International Journal for Philosophy of Religion》2007,62(3):149-169
The paper examines three themes from the recent philosophical literature on place: the status of places as “concrete universals”;
the narratively mediated agency of places; and the various ways in which human identity proves to be relative to place. I
argue that these themes throw into new relief a set of correlative issues in philosophical theology concerning, respectively,
God’s supra-individuality, God’s status as a final cause, and the divine grounding of human identity. On this basis, the paper
proposes that knowledge of place is analogous to, and partly constitutive of, knowledge of God. 相似文献
19.
Christina M. Gschwandtner 《Continental Philosophy Review》2007,40(3):231-249
In this article I examine Jean-Luc Marion's two-fold criticism of Emmanuel Levinas’ philosophy of other and self, namely that
Levinas remains unable to overcome ontological difference in Totality and Infinity and does so successfully only with the notion of the appeal in Otherwise than Being and that his account of alterity is ambiguous in failing to distinguish clearly between human and divine other. I outline
Levinas’ response to this criticism and then critically examine Marion's own account of subjectivity that attempts to go beyond
Levinas in its emphasis on a pure or anonymous appeal. I criticize this move as rather problematic and turn instead back to
Levinas for a more convincing account of the relations between self, human other, and God. In this context, I also show that
Levinas in fact draws quite careful distinctions between human and divine others. 相似文献
20.
《Reformation & Renaissance Review》2013,15(3):315-341
AbstractThe theology of Lucas Trelcatius, Jr belongs to both the broader trajectory of developing Reformed, academic formulation in the era of early orthodoxy and the carefully defined program of the Leiden University. Its way of arguing the ‘locus' on God provides an index to the nature and character of these formulations and, specifically, to issues of sources and method as well as to the still-debated questions of degree of metaphysical interest and the status of the doctrine of the Trinity. The present essay finds claims of excessive metaphysical ‘speculation’ and of de-emphasis on the doctrine of the Trinity unfounded. 相似文献