首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 62 毫秒
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
The role of hemispheric specialization in the analysis of Stroop stimuli   总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1  
  相似文献   

9.
This paper investigates the mathematical consequences of a number of related empirical laws, exemplified by
Pax;by = P(ξa)(ξx);(ξb)(ξy)
where a, x, b, y, and ξ are real numbers, and Pax;by is the probability of choosing the two-dimensional object (a, x) in the set {(a, x), (b, y)}. A variety of results is derived showing that, in the presence of such laws, the class of feasible models for choice data is considerably reduced. In particular, it is shown that the above law, together with the “additive conjoint” form
Pax;by = F[l(a) + r(x), l(b) + r(y)]
(where F, l, and r are unspecified except for continuity and monotonicity properties), requires the choice probabilities to possess one of the following three analytic forms:
Pax;by = Gaβ + δxβbβ + δyβ, β ≠ 0
;
Pax;by = G(aβxγ/bβyγ), β + γ ≠ 0
;
Pax;by = Q0(a/x, b/y)
.  相似文献   

10.
By a Thurstone Case III representation for binary symmetric choice probabilities Px,y we mean that there exist functions F, μ, σ > 0 such that Px,y = F[(μ(x) ? μ(y))2(x) + σ2(y))12]. We show that the constraint σ = constant, or μ = ασ + β, α ≠ 0, is both necessary and sufficient for a Thurstone Case III representation to be Fechnerian, i.e., to be reexpressable as as Px,y = G(u(x) ? u(y)) for some suitably chosen functions G, u.  相似文献   

11.
This paper discusses two “nondecomposable” conjoint measurement representations for an asymmetric binary relation ? on a product set A × X, namely (a, x) ? (b, y) iff f1(a) + g1(a)g2(x) > f1(b) + g1(b)g2(y), and (a, x) ? (b, y) iff f1(a) + f2(x) + g1(a)g2(x) > f1(b) + f2(y) + g1(b)g2(y). Difficulties in developing axioms for ? on A × X which imply these representations in a general formulation have led to their examination from the standpoint of bisymmetric structures based on applications of a binary operation to A × X. Depending on context, the binary operation may refer to concatenation, extensive or intensive averaging, gambles based on an uncertain chance event, or to some other interpretable process. Independence axioms which are necessary and sufficient for the special representations within the context of bisymmetric structures are presented.  相似文献   

12.
Let A, B be two sets, with B ? A × A, and ≤ a binary relation on B. The problem analyzed here is that of the existence of a mapping u: AR, satisfying:
(a,b) ? (a?,b?)iff∨∧ μ(b) ? μ(a) ? μ(b?) ? μ(a?)
whenever (a, b), (a′, b′) ∈ B. In earlier discussions of this problem, it is usually assumed that B is connected on A. Here, we only assume that B satisfies a certain convexity property. The resulting system provides an appropriate axiomatization of Fechner's scaling procedures. The independence of axioms is discussed. A more general representation is also analyzed:
(a,b) ? (a?,b?)iff∨∧ F[μ(b), μ(a)] ? F[μb?]
, where F is strictly increasing in the first argument, and strictly decreasing in the second. Sufficient conditions are presented, and a proof of the representation theorem is given.  相似文献   

13.
Dzhafarov [(2002). Multidimensional Fechnerian scaling: Pairwise comparisons, regular minimality, and nonconstant self-similarity. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 46, 583-608] claims that Regular Minimality (RM) is a fundamental property of “same-different” discrimination probabilities and supports his claim with some empirical evidence. The key feature of RM is that the mapping, h, between two observation areas based on minimum discrimination probability is invertible. Dzhafarov [(2003a). Thurstonian-type representations for “same-different” discriminations: Deterministic decisions and independent images. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 47, 184-204; (2003b). Thurstonian-type representations for “same-different” discriminations: Probabilistic decisions and interdependent images. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 47, 229-243] also demonstrates that well-behaved Thurstonian models of “same-different” judgments are incompatible with RM and Nonconstant Self-Similarity (NCSS). There is extensive empirical support for the latter. Stimulus and neural sources of perceptual noise are discussed and two points are made:
Point 1: Models that require discrimination probabilities for noisy stimuli to possess the property that h is invertible would be too restrictive.
Point 2: In the absence of stimulus noise, violations of RM may be so subtle that their detection would be unlikely.
  相似文献   

14.
Three neural signal models of increment threshold detection are compared. All assume that the criterion for threshold is the attainment of a critical, minimum neural signal (or difference between two neural signals), and that the signal due to a test flash of intensity λ in the absence of a background light is λ(λ + σ) (where σ is the semi-saturation constant). The models differ in the manner in which a background light of intensity θ is assumed to affect the signal. One model (due to Alpern et al., 1970a, Alpern et al., 1970b, Alpern et al., 1970c) assumes that the test flash signal, λ(λ + σ), is attenuated by the multiplicative factor θD(θ + θD) (where θD is a constant interpreted as sensory noise); another model specifies that the test flash signal is simply reduced (by subtraction) by the amount θ(θ + K) (K a constant). One main result of this paper is that in the absence of pigment bleaching, these two models imply indistinguishable increment threshold functions. Further, a necessary and sufficient condition for each model guaranteeing the absence of saturation with steady backgrounds is found to be empirically satisfied. A third model is considered where the background field is assumed both to contribute to the neural signal and simultaneously to attenuate it (via a gain change). These assumptions are closely related to theoretical accounts of color induction and color perception. Though this model needs further investigation, it appears to be in better accord with actual increment threshold data than the others.  相似文献   

15.
Let (M1, f), (M2, g) be mixture sets and let ? be a binary preference relation on M1 × M2. By using the concept of positive-difference structures, necessary and sufficient conditions are given for the existence of a real-valued utility function u on M1 × M2 which represents ? and possesses the bilinearity property
u(?(α, x1,x2),g(β, y1, y2))=αu(x1, g(βy1, y2))+(1 ? α) u(x2, g(β, y1, y2))=βu(?(α,x1, x2),y1)+(1 ? β) u(?(α,x1, x2),y2)
, for all α, β ∈ [0, 1], all x1, x2M1 and all y1, y2M2. Moreover, uniqueness up to positive linear transformations can be proved for those utility functions. Finally an outline is given of applications of these results in expected utility theory.  相似文献   

16.
17.
This work extend to residuated lattices the results of [7]. It also provides a possible generalization to this context of frontal operators in the sense of [9]. Let L be a residuated lattice, and f : L k ?? L a function. We give a necessary and sufficient condition for f to be compatible with respect to every congruence on L. We use this characterization of compatible functions in order to prove that the variety of residuated lattices is locally affine complete. We study some compatible functions on residuated lattices which are a generalization of frontal operators. We also give conditions for two operations P(x, y) and Q(x, y) on a residuated lattice L which imply that the function ${x \mapsto min\{y \in L : P(x, y) \leq Q(x, y)\}}$ when defined, is equational and compatible. Finally we discuss the affine completeness of residuated lattices equipped with some additional operators.  相似文献   

18.
Compatible and incompatible stimulus-response arrangements were compared using an eight choice reaction time task. With the compatible stimulus-response conditions, a stimulus was responded to quickly if it was:
1.
(1) adjacent to the ends or mid-line of the stimulus display,  相似文献   

19.
A relational structure is said to be of scale type (M,N) iff M is the largest degree of homogeneity and N the least degree of uniqueness (Narens, 1981a, Narens, 1981b) of its automorphism group.Roberts (in Proceedings of the first Hoboken Symposium on graph theory, New York: Wiley, 1984; in Proceedings of the fifth international conference on graph theory and its applications, New York: Wiley, 1984) has shown that such a structure on the reals is either ordinal or M is less than the order of at least one defining relation (Theorem 1.2). A scheme for characterizing N is outlined in Theorem 1.3. The remainder of the paper studies the scale type of concatenation structures 〈X, ?, ° 〉, where ? is a total ordering and ° is a monotonic operation. Section 2 establishes that for concatenation structures with M>0 and N<∞ the only scale types are (1,1), (1,2), and (2,2), and the structures for the last two are always idempotent. Section 3 is concerned with such structures on the real numbers (i.e., candidates for representations), and it uses general results of Narens for real relational structures of scale type (M, M) (Theorem 3.1) and of Alper (Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 1985, 29, 73–81) for scale type (1, 2) (Theorem 3.2). For M>0, concatenation structures are all isomorphic to numerical ones for which the operation can be written x°y = yf(xy), where f is strictly increasing and f(x)x is strictly decreasing (unit structures). The equation f(x?)=f(x)? is satisfied for all x as follows: for and only for ? = 1 in the (1,1) case; for and only for ?=kn, k > 0 fixed, and n ranging over the integers, in the (1, 2) case; and for all ?>0 in the (2, 2) case (Theorems 3.9, 3.12, and 3.13). Section 4 examines relations between concatenation catenation and conjoint structures, including the operation induced on one component by the ordering of a conjoint structure and the concept of an operation on one component being distributive in a conjoint structure. The results, which are mainly of interest in proving other results, are mostly formulated in terms of the set of right translations of the induced operation. In Section 5 we consider the existence of representations of concatenation structures. The case of positive ones was dealt with earlier (Narens & Luce (Journal of Pure & Applied Algebra27, 1983, 197–233). For idempotent ones, closure, density, solvability, and Archimedean are shown to be sufficient (Theorem 5.1). The rest of the section is concerned with incomplete results having to do with the representation of cases with M>0. A variety of special conditions, many suggested by the conjoint equivalent of a concatenation structure, are studied in Section 6. The major result (Theorem 6.4) is that most of these concepts are equivalent to bisymmetry for idempotent structures that are closed, dense, solvable, and Dedekind complete. This result is important in Section 7, which is devoted to a general theory of scale type (2, 2) for the utility of gambles. The representation is a generalization of the usual SEU model which embodies a distinctly bounded form of rationality; by the results of Section 6 it reduces to the fully rational SEU model when rationality is extended beyond the simplest equivalences. Theorem 7.3 establishes that under plausible smoothness conditions, the ratio scale case does not introduce anything different from the (2, 2) case. It is shown that this theory is closely related to, but somewhat more general, than Kahneman and Tversky's (Econometrica47, 1979, 263–291) prospect theory.  相似文献   

20.
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号