共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
In the current paper, we re-examine how abstract argumentation can be formulated in terms of labellings, and how the resulting theory can be applied in the field of modal logic. In particular, we are able to express the (complete) extensions of an argumentation framework as models of a set of modal logic formulas that represents the argumentation framework. Using this approach, it becomes possible to define the grounded extension in terms of modal logic entailment. 相似文献
2.
Walton's Argumentation Schemes for Presumptive Reasoning: A Critique and Development 总被引:3,自引:0,他引:3
J. Anthony Blair 《Argumentation》2001,15(4):365-379
The aim of the paper is to advance the theory of argument or inference schemes by suggesting answers to questions raised by Walton's Argumentation Schemes for Presumptive Reasoning (1996), specifically on: the relation between argument and reasoning; distinguishing deductive from presumptive schemes, the origin of schemes and the probative force of their use; and the motivation and justification for their associated critical questions. 相似文献
3.
This study applies the concept of reported speech advanced by the renowned Russian literary scholar Mikhail Bakhtin to compare the argumentative styles of Mainland China and Taiwan. These societies in question are considered by many scholars as sharing the same argumentative style. The study reports that the Mainland debaters more frequently than the Taiwanese debaters maintained the authenticity of the quotations cited from ancient Confucian sources, whereas Taiwanese debaters paraphrased more frequently. On the other hand, this difference cannot be found when debaters quoted from sources other than Ancient Confucians. The findings, according to Bakhtin, imply a contrast of monologic and dialogic tendencies toward authority, which results in a style difference between Mainland and Taiwan argumentation. 相似文献
4.
John F. Halpin 《Erkenntnis》2003,58(2):137-168
An acceptable empiricist account of laws of nature would havesignificant implications for a number of philosophical projects. For example, such an account may vitiate argumentsthat the fundamental constants of nature are divinelydesigned so that laws produce a life permittinguniverse. On an empiricist account, laws do not produce the universe but are designed by us to systematize theevents of a universe which does in fact contain life; so any ``fine tuning' of natural law has a naturalistic explanation.But there are problems for the empiricist project. This paper develops a ``perspectival' version of the Humean bestsystem approach and argues that this version solves the standard problems faced by the empiricist project.Furthermore, the paper argues, this version is best able to answer the proponents of divine design while leaving scientificlaw a suitably objective matter.[I]t is possible tocondense the enormous mass of results to a large extent – that is to find laws which summarize ...Richard Feynman (1963)It has become fashionable in some circles to argue thatscience is ultimately a sham, that we scientists read order into nature, not out of nature, and that the laws of physicsare our laws, not nature's. I believe this is arrant nonsense. You would be hard-pressed to convince a physicist thatNewton's inverse square law of gravitation is a purely cultural concoction. The laws of physics, I submit, reallyexist in the world out there, and the job of the scientist is to uncover them, not invent them. True, at any giventime, the laws you find in the textbooks are tentative and approximate, but they mirror, albeit imperfectly, a reallyexisting order in the physical world. Of course, many scientists do not recognize that in accepting the reality of anorder in nature-the existence of laws `out there' – they are adopting a theological world view. P. C. W. Davies (1995) 相似文献
5.
6.
《认知与教导》2013,31(4):285-327
The two studies presented here examine processes of theory revision and strategy change that occur when preadolescent subjects engage in self-directed exploration of a problem domain. The microgenetic method, involving frequent encounters with the same tasks over a period of months, permitted detailed observation of the change process. Not only do theories themselves undergo revision but also the reasoning strategies subjects use to generate new knowledge show improvement over time. The cross-domain feature of the research made it possible to establish that these strategies show co-development when subjects are observed over time working in two different content domains. The research thus accomplishes the objective of more clearly distinguishing the reasoning competencies that are developing from the domain-specific contexts in which they are situated. 相似文献
7.
Plausible (eikotic) reasoning known from ancient Greek (late Academic) skeptical philosophy is shown to be a clear notion that can be analyzed by argumentation methods, and that is important for argumentation studies. It is shown how there is a continuous thread running from the Sophists to the skeptical philosopher Carneades, through remarks of Locke and Bentham on the subject, to recent research in artificial intelligence. Eleven characteristics of plausible reasoning are specified by analyzing key examples of it recognized as important in ancient Greek skeptical philosophy using an artificial intelligence model called the Carneades Argumentation System (CAS). By applying CAS to ancient examples it is shown how plausible reasoning is especially useful for gaining a better understanding of evidential reasoning in law, and argued that it can also be applied to everyday argumentation. Our analysis of the snake and rope example of Carneades is also used to point out some ways CAS needs to be extended if it is to more fully model the views of this ancient philosopher on argumentation. 相似文献
8.
9.
10.
《认知与教导》2013,31(4):379-432
In this study we examined the discourse components, interaction patterns, and reasoning complexity of 4 groups of 12 Grade 8 students in 2 science classrooms as they constructed mental models of the nature of matter, both on their own and with teacher guidance. Interactions within peer and teacher-guided small group discussions were videotaped and audiotaped, transcribed, and analyzed in a variety of ways. The key act of participants in both peer and teacher-guided groups was working with weak or incomplete ideas until they improved. How this was accomplished differed somewhat depending on the presence or absence of a teacher in the discussion. Teachers acted as a catalyst in discussions, prompting students to expand and clarify their thinking without providing direct information. Teacher-guided discussions were a more efficient means of attaining higher levels of reasoning and higher quality explanations, but peer discussions tended to be more generative and exploratory. Students' discourse was more varied within peer groups, and some peer groups attained higher levels of reasoning on their own. Ideas for using the results of these analyses to develop teachers' and students' collaborative scientific reasoning skills are presented. 相似文献
11.
Rogério Gerspacher 《Axiomathes》2018,28(1):63-71
It is easy to accept that scientific reasoning cannot determine the characteristics of subjective experiences in cases like Broad’s archangel or Jackson’s Mary. The author questions why this seems to be evident and discusses the differences between these cases and ordinary scientific work, where future states of studied systems can be predicted in phenomenal terms. He concludes that important limitations of scientific reasoning are due to the inadequacy of human sensorial apparatus for representing physical reality. Such inadequacies were more evident in Mary’s case, but are always present, and entail the existence of the explanatory gap. 相似文献
12.
The value of argumentation in science education has become internationally recognised and has been the subject of many research
studies in recent years. Successful introduction of argumentation activities in learning contexts involves extending teaching
goals beyond the understanding of facts and concepts, to include an emphasis on cognitive and metacognitive processes, epistemic
criteria and reasoning. The authors focus on the difficulties inherent in shifting a tradition of teaching from one dominated
by authoritative exposition to one that is more dialogic, involving small-group discussion based on tasks that stimulate argumentation.
The paper focuses on how argumentation activities have been designed in school science. Examples of classroom dialogue where
teachers adopt the frameworks/plans are analysed to show how argumentation processes are scaffolded. The analysis shows that
several layers of interpretation are needed and these layers need to be aligned for successful implementation. 相似文献
13.
Simon Wolf 《Argumentation》2010,24(1):19-40
In his works on argumentation, Aristotle develops three main forms: apodeictical, dialectical, and rhetorical argumentation;
dialectic is subdivided into several subspecies. The purpose of this paper is to discuss all of the forms described by Aristotle,
to examine their differences and to point out their interrelations. This leads to an examination of the differentiating criteria
and their applicability in the case of each argumentation form—and in particular to the question regarding the number of criteria
that are necessary to describe each form clearly and unambiguously. It is argued that Aristotle’s works on argumentation contain
an implicit system of argumentation forms that is based on no more than three criteria. 相似文献
14.
15.
16.
Beth Innocenti Manolescu 《Argumentation》2007,21(4):379-395
Shame appeals may be both relevant to and make possible argumentation with reluctant addressees. I propose a normative pragmatic
model of practical reasoning involved in shame appeals and show that its explanatory power exceeds that of a more traditional
account of an underlying practical inference structure. I also illustrate that analyzing the formal propriety of shame appeals
offers a more complete explanation of their normative pragmatic force than an application of rules for dialogue types. 相似文献
17.
18.
Axel Arturo Barceló Aspeitia 《Argumentation》2012,26(3):355-368
In this essay, I will argue that images can play a substantial role in argumentation: exploiting information from the context, they can contribute directly and substantially to the communication of the propositions that play the roles of premises and conclusion. Furthermore, they can achieve this directly, i.e. without the need of verbalization. I will ground this claim by presenting and analyzing some arguments where images are essential to the argumentation process. 相似文献
19.
20.