共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
PETER D. KLEIN 《Philosophy and phenomenological research》2004,68(1):166-171
There are many things that could be wrong with foundationalism. For example, some have claimed that a so‐called basic belief cannot be both 1) a reason for non‐basic beliefs and 2) such that it cannot be provided with at least prima facie justification.1 If something is a reason, they say, then that something has to be a proposition (or sufficiently proposition‐like) and if it is a proposition (or sufficiently proposition‐like), then it is the kind of thing that requires a reason in order to be even prima facie justified.2 Another reason that some give for rejecting normative foundationalism is that it leads directly to skepticism.3 There is no way, they claim, to move from so‐called basic propositions (typically given as first person introspective reports) to “external world” propositions by employing normatively acceptable principles of reasoning.4 Still others have thought that the invention of a nonrea‐soned reason was as ad hoc as the invention of an unmoved mover.5 相似文献
2.
Mylan Engel Jr. 《Metaphilosophy》2014,45(2):146-160
As we trace a chain of reasoning backward, it must ultimately do one of four things: (i) end in an unjustified belief, (ii) continue infinitely, (iii) form a circle, or (iv) end in an immediately justified basic belief. This article defends positism—the view that, in certain circumstances, type‐(i) chains can justify us in holding their target beliefs. One of the assumptions that generates the epistemic regress problem is: (A) Person S is mediately justified in believing p iff (1) S has a doxastic reason q for p and (2) S is justified in believing q. Assumption (A) presupposes that reasoning is only justification transmitting, not justification generating. The article rejects (A) and argues that, in certain circumstances, reasoning itself is justification generating, even if that from which one is reasoning is not itself justified. It concludes by comparing positism with its infinitist, coherentist, and foundationalist rivals, acknowledging what is right about these other views. 相似文献
3.
Michael Rescorla 《Australasian journal of philosophy》2013,91(1):43-60
Dialectical egalitarianism holds that every asserted proposition requires defence when challenged by an interlocutor. This view apparently generates a vicious ‘regress of justifications’, since an interlocutor can challenge the premises through which a speaker defends her original assertion, and so on ad infinitum. To halt the regress, dialectical foundationalists such as Adler, Brandom, Leite, and Williams propose that some propositions require no defence in the light of mere requests for justification. I argue that the putative regress is not worrisome and that egalitarianism can handle it quite satisfactorily. I also defend a positive view that combines an anti-foundationalist conception of dialectical interaction with a foundationalist conception of epistemic justification. 相似文献
4.
Andrew D. Cling 《Metaphilosophy》2014,45(2):161-171
There are important similarities between the epistemic regress problem and the problem of the criterion. Each turns on plausible principles stating that epistemic reasons must be supported by epistemic reasons but that having reasons is impossible if that requires having endless regresses of reasons. These principles are incompatible with the possibility of reasons, so each problem is a paradox. Whether there can be an antiskeptical solution to these paradoxes depends upon the kinds of reasons that we need in order to attain our epistemic goals. This article explains the problems and considers the ways in which two different conceptions of human flourishing support the value of different kinds of reasons. One conception requires reasons that allow an easy solution to these paradoxes. The other—rational autonomy—requires reasons that depend upon endless regresses. So we cannot have the kinds of fully transparent reasons required for rational autonomy. 相似文献
5.
José L. Zalabardo 《Synthese》2006,148(1):135-169
In this paper I assess the two central ingredients of Laurence BonJour’s position on empirical knowledge that have survived
the transition from his earlier coherentist views to his current endorsement of the doctrine of the given: his construal of
the problem of the epistemic regress and his rejection of an internalist solution to the problem. The bulk of the paper is
devoted to a critical assessment of BonJour’s arguments against externalism. I argue that they fail to put real pressure on
externalism, as they rely on a highly questionable conception of epistemic rationality and responsibility. Then, more briefly,
I take issue with BonJour’s endorsement of the irrelevance thesis—the claim that even if externalism were true it would not offer a satisfactory solution to the epistemic regress problem.
I contend that he is not entitled to subscribe this thesis unless he is prepared to abandon his construal of the problem.
*I have presented some of this material at UCL, Trinity College Dublin and the 10th Italo-Spanish meeting of Analytic Philosophy,
held in Pamplona. I am grateful to these audiences. 相似文献
6.
Andrew Norman 《The Philosophical quarterly》1997,47(189):477-494
Existing solutions to the epistemic regress problem, and the theories of justification built upon them, are inadequate, for they fail to diagnose the root source of the problem. The problem is rooted in our attachment to a pernicious dogma of modern epistemology: the idea that a judgement must be supported by some kind of reason or evidence to be justified. The epistemic analogue of the doctrine of original sin, this idea renders every judgement in need of redemption – guilty until shown to be innocent – distorting our understanding of reason at a very deep level, and preventing us from conceptualizing a satisfactory solution to the problem. If we opt for a more context–sensitive mechanism for assigning default epistemic status, however, we get a more plausible picture of justification, an epistemology more in tune with epistemic practice, and an elegant solution to the regress problem. 相似文献
7.
8.
We discuss two objections that foundationalists have raised against infinite chains of probabilistic justification. We demonstrate
that neither of the objections can be maintained.
Presented by Hannes Leitgeb 相似文献
9.
Robert Jubb 《Res Publica》2009,15(4):337-353
In this paper, I seek to undermine G.A. Cohen’s polemical use of a metaethical claim he makes in his article, ‘Facts and Principles’,
by arguing that that use requires an unsustainable equivocation between epistemic and logical grounding. I begin by distinguishing
three theses that Cohen has offered during the course of his critique of Rawls and contractualism more generally, the foundationalism
about grounding thesis, the justice as non-regulative thesis, and the justice as all-encompassing thesis, and briefly argue
that they are analytically independent of each other. I then offer an outline of the foundationalism about grounding thesis,
characterising it, as Cohen does, as a demand of logic. That thesis claims that whenever a normative principle is dependent
on a fact, it is so dependent in virtue of some other principle. I then argue that although this is true as a matter of logic,
it, as Cohen admits, cannot be true of actual justifications, since logic cannot tell us anything about the truth as opposed
to the validity of arguments. Facts about a justification cannot then be decisive for whether or not a given argument violates
the foundationalism about grounding thesis. As long as, independently of actual justifications, theorists can point to plausible
logically grounding principles, as I argue contractualists can, Cohen’s thesis lacks critical bite. 相似文献
10.
11.
12.
Victoria S. Harrison 《Sophia》2012,51(1):71-86
In our increasingly multicultural society there is an urgent need for a theory that is capable of making sense of the various
philosophical difficulties presented by ethical and religious diversity—difficulties that, at first sight, seem to be remarkably
similar. Given this similarity, a theory that successfully accounted for the difficulties raised by one form of plurality
might also be of help in addressing those raised by the other, especially as ethical belief systems are often inextricably
linked with religious belief systems. This article adumbrates a theory that is suitably sensitive to the challenge posed by
cultural diversity, and that is respectful of ethical and religious differences. The theory, called “internalist pluralism,”
provides a philosophical account of the widely differing claims made by religious believers resulting from the tremendous
diversity of belief systems, while simultaneously yielding a novel perspective on ethical plurality. Internalist pluralism
is based on Hilary Putnam’s theory of internal realism. This article is not concerned to defend internal realism against its
critics, although such defense is clearly required if the theory is to be adopted. Its more modest aim is to show that internal
realism has a distinctive voice to add to the current debate about how best to understand religious and ethical diversity. 相似文献
13.
Philosophical Studies - 相似文献
14.
Scott Stapleford 《Ratio》2016,29(3):283-297
Many deontologists explain the epistemic value of justification in terms of its instrumental role in promoting truth – the original source of value in the epistemic domain. The swamping problem for truth monism appears to make this position indefensible, at least for those monists who maintain the superiority of knowledge to merely true belief. I propose a new solution to the swamping problem that allows monists to maintain the greater epistemic value of knowledge over merely true belief. My trick is to deny the swamping premise itself. 相似文献
15.
16.
17.
Philosophical Studies - The New Evil Demon Problem presents a serious challenge to externalist theories of epistemic justification. In recent years, externalists have developed a number of... 相似文献
18.
David Christensen 《Philosophy and phenomenological research》2021,103(3):501-517
Many writers have recently urged that the epistemic rationality of beliefs can depend on broadly pragmatic (as opposed to truth-directed) factors. Taken to an extreme, this line of thought leads to a view on which there is no such thing as a distinctive epistemic form of rationality. A series of papers by Susanna Rinard develops the view that something like our traditional notion of pragmatic rationality is all that is needed to account for the rationality of beliefs. This approach has undeniable attractions. But examining different versions of the approach uncovers problems. The problems help reveal why epistemic rationality is an indispensable part of understanding rationality—not only of beliefs, but of actions. We may or may not end up wanting to make a place, in our theories of epistemic rationality, for factors such as the practical or moral consequences of having beliefs. But a purely pragmatic notion of rationality—one that’s stripped of any component of distinctively epistemic evaluation—cannot do all the work that we need done. 相似文献
19.
20.
Laurence BonJour 《No?s (Detroit, Mich.)》1999,33(S13):229-249