共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
2.
3.
Arrigo JM 《Science and engineering ethics》2004,10(3):543-572
Following the September 2001 terrorist attacks on the United States, much support for torture interrogation of terrorists
has emerged in the public forum, largely based on the “ticking bomb” scenario. Although deontological and virtue ethics provide
incisive arguments against torture, they do not speak directly to scientists and government officials responsible for national
security in a utilitarian framework. Drawing from criminology, organizational theory, social psychology, the historical record,
and my interviews with military professionals, I assess the potential of an official U.S. program of torture interrogation
from a practical perspective. The central element of program design is a sound causal model relating input to output. I explore
three principal models of how torture interrogation leads to truth: the animal instinct model, the cognitive failure model, and the data processing model. These models show why torture interrogation fails overall as a counterterrorist tactic. They also expose the processes that
lead from a precision torture interrogation program to breakdowns in key institutions—health care, biomedical research, police,
judiciary, and military. The breakdowns evolve from institutional dynamics that are independent of the original moral rationale.
The counterargument, of course, is that in a society destroyed by terrorism there will be nothing to repair. That is why the
actual causal mechanism of torture interrogation in curtailing terrorism must be elucidated by utilitarians rather than presumed. 相似文献
4.
5.
Indecent medicine: in defense of the absolute prohibition against physician participation in torture
Matthews RS 《The American journal of bioethics : AJOB》2006,6(3):W34-W44
In a recent article, Gross (2004) argues that physicians in decent societies have a civic duty to aid in the torturing of suspected terrorists during emergency conditions. The argument presupposes a communitarian society in which considerations of common good override questions of individual rights, but it is also utilitarian. In the event that there is a ticking bomb and no other alternative available for defusing it, torture must be used, and physicians must play their part. In an earlier article, Jones (1980) also argues in favour of physician participation in torture, going so far as to enthusiastically endorse the allocation of research resources as well to ensure that the ability to meet emergency situations is as efficient as scientifically possible. I argue against both these views and defend the absolute prohibition against torture generally, and against any participation by physicians in particular. I show that these arguments are incompatible with liberal or decent societies, and that the institutional requirements for making torture effective would constitute an unacceptable degradation both of medical ethics and practice, as well as of political institutions in general. 相似文献
6.
Atkinson GM 《International philosophical quarterly : IPQ》1974,14(3):347-362
7.
In this article, we discuss the range of concerns people weigh when evaluating the acceptability of harmful actions and propose a new perspective on the relationship between harm and morality. With this aim, we examine Kelly, Stich, Haley, Eng and Fessler’s [Kelly, D., Stich, S., Haley, K., Eng, S., & Fessler, D. (2007). Harm, affect, and the moral/conventional distinction. Mind and Language, 22, 117-131] recent claim that, contrary to Turiel and associates, people do not judge harm to be authority independent and general in scope in the context of complex harmful scenarios (e.g., prisoner interrogation, military training). In a modified replication of their study, we examined participants’ judgments of harmful actions in these contexts by taking into account their explanations for their judgments. We claim that both in terms of participants’ judgments and rationales, the results largely confirm our hypothesis that actions involving harm andinjustice or rights violation are judged to be authority independent and general in scope, which is a modification of Turiel’s traditional hypothesis. 相似文献
8.
Pastoral Psychology - 相似文献
9.
10.
Phil Brown 《Philosophical Studies》2013,163(3):627-636
Despite much discussion over the existence of moral facts, metaethicists have largely ignored the related question of their possibility. This paper addresses the issue from the moral error theorist’s perspective, and shows how the arguments that error theorists have produced against the existence of moral facts at this world, if sound, also show that moral facts are impossible, at least at worlds non-morally identical to our own and, on some versions of the error theory, at any world. So error theorists’ arguments warrant a stronger conclusion than has previously been noticed. This may appear to make them vulnerable to counterarguments that take the possibility of moral facts as a premise. However, I show that any such arguments would be question-begging. 相似文献
11.
Houston AI 《Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior》1982,38(1):109-111
Allen (1981) claims to have established the formal validity of a power-function generalization of the matching law. This paper argues that Allen's proof is not correct when schedules are presented in pairs and that his initial assumptions are too restrictive when all schedules are simultaneously available. 相似文献
12.
13.
Michael Moehler 《Philosophical Studies》2014,167(2):431-451
In The Order of Public Reason (2011a), Gerald Gaus rejects the instrumental approach to morality as a viable account of social morality. Gaus’ rejection of the instrumental approach to morality, and his own moral theory, raise important foundational questions concerning the adequate scope of instrumental morality. In this article, I address some of these questions and I argue that Gaus’ rejection of the instrumental approach to morality stems primarily from a common but inadequate application of this approach. The scope of instrumental morality, and especially the scope of pure moral instrumentalism, is limited. The purely instrumental approach to morality can be applied fruitfully to moral philosophy only in situations of extreme pluralism in which moral reasoning is reduced to instrumental reasoning, because the members of a society do not share, as assumed by traditional moral theories, a consensus on moral ideals as a basis for the derivation of social moral rules, but only an end that they aim to reach. Based on this understanding, I develop a comprehensive two-level contractarian theory that integrates traditional morality with instrumental morality. I argue that this theory, if implemented, is most promising for securing mutually beneficial peaceful long-term cooperation in deeply pluralistic societies, as compared to cooperation in a non-moralized state of nature. 相似文献
14.
Forge J 《Science and engineering ethics》2004,10(3):531-542
I ask whether weapons research is ever justified. Weapons research is identified as the business of the engineer. It is argued
that the engineer has responsibility for the uses to which the tools that he designs can be put, and that responsibility extends
to the use of weapons. It is maintained that there are no inherently defensive weapons, and hence there is no such thing as
‘defensive’ weapons research. The issue then is what responsibilities as a professional the engineer has in regard to such
research. An account is given to ground the injunction not to provide the means to harm as a duty for the engineers. This
account is not, however, absolutist, and as such it allows justifiable exceptions. The answer to my question is thus not that
weapons research is never justified but there must be a strong assurance that the results will only be used as a just means
in a just cause. 相似文献
15.
16.
The ideal of scientific openness — i.e. the idea that scientific information should be freely accessible to interested parties — is strongly supported throughout the scientific community. At the same time, however, this ideal does not appear to be absolute in the everyday practice of science. In order to get the credit for new scientific advances, scientists often keep information to themselves. Also, it is common practice to withhold information obtained in commissioned research when the scientist has agreed with his or her employer to do so. The secrecy may be intended for ever, as in the military area, but also temporarily until a patent application has been made. The paper explores to what extent such secrecy is undesirable, as seems to be suggested by the ideal of scientific openness. Should this ideal be interpreted as having certain exceptions which make the above-mentioned practices acceptable? Are there, on closer inspection, good arguments for the ideal of scientific openness, and for officially upholding it? Possible versions of the ideal of scientific openness are explored and the issue is found to be rather complex, allowing for wide variations depending on the acting parties, beneficiaries, types of information and moral requirements involved. We conclude that the arguments usually given in favour of this ideal are weaker than what seems to be generally believed, and that, on closer inspection, they leave plenty of room for exceptions to it. These exceptions only partly cover the actual practice of withholding scientific information, and there may still be good reason to advocate, teach and enforce the ideal of scientific openness within the scientific community. 相似文献
17.
18.
Philosophical Studies - We often act in ways that create duties for ourselves: we adopt a child and become obligated to raise and educate her. We also sometimes act in ways that eliminate duties:... 相似文献
19.
Philosophical Studies - Most Kantian constructivists try to ground universal duties of interpersonal morality in certain interactions between individuals, such as communication, argumentation,... 相似文献
20.
Kuo L 《The Southern journal of philosophy》1989,27(3):361-380