共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
Robert A. Pearlman Steven H. Miles Robert M. Arnold 《Theoretical medicine and bioethics》1993,14(3):197-210
Empirical research pertaining to cardiopulmonary resuscitation (CPR), clinician behaviors related to do-not-resuscitate (DNR) orders and substituted judgment suggests potential contributions to medical ethics. Research quantifying the likelihood of surviving CPR points to the need for further philosophical analysis of the limitations of the patient autonomy in decision making, the nature and definition of medical futility, and the relationship between futility and professional standards. Research on DNR orders has identified barriers to the goal of patient involvement in these life and death discussions. The initial data on surrogate decision making also points to the need for a reexamination of the moral basis for substituted judgment, the moral authority of proxy decision making and the second-order status of the best interests standard. These examples of empirical research suggest that an interplay between empirical research, ethical analysis and policy development may represent a new form of interdisciplinary scholarship to improve clinical medicine. 相似文献
2.
William J. Donnelly 《Theoretical medicine and bioethics》1994,15(2):141-148
Many alternatives or supplements to principalism seek to reconnect medical ethics with the thoughts, feelings, and motivations of the persons directly involved in ethically troublesome situations. This shift of attention, from deeds to doers, from principles to principals, acknowledges the importance of the moral agents involved in the situation — particular practitioners, patients, and families. Taking into account the subjective, lived experience of moral decision-making parallels recent efforts in the teaching of medicine to give the patient's subjectivity — his or her personal experience of being sick or disabled — epistemological parity with scientific medicine's objective, biomedically-oriented view of the person's sickness or disability.Moreover, the shift from principalism to principals signals a growing realization that ethical problems in the profession of medicine are inseparable from its practice. Philosophers and other humanists working in medicine should resist the temptation to institutionalize a professional role as solver of ethical problems, clarifier of values, or mediator of disputes and work instead to help practitioners practice medicine reflectively. 相似文献
3.
David C. Thomasma 《Theoretical medicine and bioethics》1994,15(2):93-111
There are several branches of ethics. Clinical ethics, the one closest to medical decisionmaking, can be seen as a branch of medicine itself. In this view, clinical ethics is a unitary hermeneutics. Its rule is a guideline for unifying other theories of ethics in conjunction with the clinical context. Put another way, clinical ethics interprets the clinical situation in light of a balance of other values that, while guiding the decisionmaking process, also contributes to the very weighting of those values. The case itself originates ideas, not only about which value ought to predominate in its resolution, but also provides the origin of clinical rules that can be used in other cases. These are interpretive rules. Some examples of these rules are presented as well. 相似文献
4.
A model is described for implementing a program in research ethics education in the face of federal and institutional mandates
and current resource, disciplinary, and infrastructure limitations. Also discussed are the historical background, content
and evaluation process of the workshop at the heart of the program, which reaches a diverse group of over 250 students per
year—from first-year graduate students in basic research labs to clinical fellows. The workshop addresses central issues in
both everyday laboratory ethics and in larger societal questions. Goals include improving overall awareness of ethics guidelines
and philosophy and enhancing skills in identifying and then analyzing the ethical components of situations. Pedagogies used
and their effectiveness and that of the overall workshop and extended program are addressed. Programs like these have initiated
a shift in the culture of basic research, which is a critical need given the current atmosphere. 相似文献
5.
The pluralism of methodologies and severe time constraints pose important challenges to pedagogy in clinical ethics. We designed a step-by-step student handbook to operate within such constraints and to respect the methodological pluralism of bioethics and clinical ethics. The handbook comprises six steps: Step 1: What are the facts of the case?; Step 2: What are your obligations to your patient?; Step 3: What are your obligations to third parties to your relationship with the patient?; Step 4: Do your obligations converge or conflict?; Step 5: What is the strongest objection that could be made to the identification of convergence in step 4 or the arguments in step 4? How can this objection be effectively countered?; and Step 6: How could the ethical conflict, or perceived ethical conflict, have been prevented? 相似文献
6.
Development of international guidelines for research ethics 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
Kaiser M 《Science and engineering ethics》1999,5(2):293-298
7.
8.
In this editorial contribution, two issues relevant to the question, what should be at the top of the research agenda for ethics and technology, are identified and discussed. Firstly: can, and do, engineers make a difference to the degree to which technology leads to morally desirable outcomes? What role does professional autonomy play here, and what are its limits? And secondly, what should be the scope of engineers' responsibility; that is to say, on which issues are they, as engineers, morally obliged to reflect? The research agendas proposed by the authors contributing to this special section, implicitly, give different answers to these questions. We suggest that an explicit discussion of these issues would greatly help in constructing a common research agenda. 相似文献
9.
10.
Business ethics and computer ethics: The view from Poland 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
Prof. Jacek Sojka 《Science and engineering ethics》1996,2(2):191-200
An Aristotelian approach to understanding and teaching business ethics is presented and defended. The newly emerging field
of computer ethics is also defined in an Aristotelian fashion, and an argument is made that this new field should be called
“information ethics”. It is argued that values have their roots in the life and practices of a community; therefore, morality
cannot be taught by training for a special way of reasoning. Transmission of values and norms occurs through socialization
— the process by which an individual absorbs not only values but also the whole way of life of his or her community. It follows
that business ethics and information ethics can be considered kinds of socialization into a profession: role learning and
acquiring a new self-identification. This way of understanding fields of applied ethics is especially important for their
proper development in Central-Eastern Europe because of endemic factors which are the result of recent political developments
there. 相似文献
11.
12.
In Canada, all research conducted by individuals associated with universities must be subjected to review by research ethics boards (REB). Unfortunately, decisions reached by REBs may seriously compromise the integrity of university-based research. In this paper attention will focus on how requirements of REBs and a legal department in four Canadian universities affected response rates to a survey of domestic and international students. It will be shown that in universities in which students were sent a legalistic cover letter to a mail survey, or were required to sign a consent form, lower response rates were achieved than in universities in which students were sent a relatively friendly letter. In turn, lower response rates resulted in: sample characteristics that deviated from population characteristics; a reduction in the possibility of testing research hypotheses; and increased survey costs. As a consequence, it is argued that the unreasonable demands of REBs are seriously compromising the quality of research that can be carried out on Canadian university students. 相似文献
13.
Universal compulsory service in medical research 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
Herrera CD 《Theoretical medicine and bioethics》2003,24(3):215-231
14.
浅析心理统计学教学设计中的统计意识 总被引:9,自引:0,他引:9
本文从教学设计的视角对下列两方面进行了理性的分析:(1)心理实验设计与心理统计课程的教学应逐步整合起来;(2)由于学科的特殊性,必须对统计再认识。 相似文献
15.
d'Anjou P 《Science and engineering ethics》2004,10(2):211-218
The paper addresses the integration of ethics into professional education related to the disciplines responsible for the conception
and creation of the artificial (artefactual or technology). The ontological-epistemological paradigm of those disciplines
is understood within the frame of the sciences of the artificial as established by Herbert Simon (1969). According to that
paradigm, those sciences include disciplines not only related to the production of artefacts (technology), such as engineering,
architecture, industrial design, etc, but also disciplines related to devised courses of action aimed at changing existing
situations into preferred ones, like medicine, law, education, etc. They are centered on intentional action and at their core
is the activity of design, which is their common foundation and attitude, or their common culture. The science of design becomes
the broader foundational discipline for any professions engaged in the intentional transformation of the world.
The main distinction between design disciplines and scientific ones rests on the object-project dichotomy. Indeed, contrary
to Science that sees the world as an object to be observed, Design sees the world as a project and acts upon the world through
projects, which are grounded in intentions, ends, and values. Design disciplines are meant to transform the world, or part
of it, and are teleological. Being so, they are embodied in an act that is ethical and their ontology-epistemology must be
addressed also through practical reason to resituate all professional disciplines according to their involved nature.
The paper introduces theoretical, methodological, and ethical elements to establish a model that integrates ethics into the
education of the professional disciplines, design-based disciplines, responsible for the creation of the artificial, artefactual
or technological, world. The model is articulated around the notions of ethical engagement and responsibility through the
act of design understood as action with intention situated in a project, common in all professional disciplines.
An earlier version of this paper was presented at the “Ethics and Social Responsibility in Engineering and Technology” meeting,
New Orleans, 2003. 相似文献
16.
Introduction and overview: Global information ethics 总被引:2,自引:0,他引:2
This is an introduction to a set of papers on Computer Ethics from the conference ETHICOMP95. Taken as a whole, the collection
of papers provides arguments and concepts to launch a new development in computer ethics: ‘Global Information Ethics’. A rationale
for globalization is provided, as well as some early efforts which move in that direction.
ETHICOMP95, an international conference on Computer Ethics, was held 28–30 March 1995 at De Montfort University, Leicester,
UK. Co-directors were Terrell Ward Bynum and Simon Rogerson. 相似文献
17.
Feng P 《Science and engineering ethics》2000,6(2):207-220
This paper explores the role of ethics in design. Traditionally, ethical questions have been seen as marginal issues in the
design of technology. Part of the reason for this stems from the widely held notion of technology being “out of control.”
This notion is a barrier to what I call “ethical design” because it implies that ethics has no role to play in the development
of technology. This view, however, is challenged by recent work in the field of Science and Technology Studies (STS). Looking
into the dynamics of technological change, STS scholars argue that human choices are present at every stage of a technology’s
development and, furthermore, that human values are reflected in the very design of artifacts. This alternative view suggests
that ethics can and should be included in the design process. Drawing on examples from the privacy arena. I point to some
of the potential advantages of addressing ethical concerns early on in the design of a technology. I conclude with some general
strategies for bringing ethics back into design.
A version of this paper was presented at ETHICOMP98, the Fourth International Conference on Ethical Issues of Information
Technology, March 25–27, 1998, Erasmus University, the Netherlands.
Patrick Feng is a Ph.D. student in the Science and Technology Studies Department at Rensselaer. His research focuses on the
development of technical standards that are designed to address social values such as privacy and trust. 相似文献
18.
In this article, I consider the virtual absence of an African voice and perspective in global discourses of medical research ethics against the backdrop of the high burden of diseases and epidemics on the continent and the fact that the continent is actually the scene of numerous and sundry medical research studies. I consider some reasons for this state of affairs as well as how the situation might be redressed. Using examples from the HIV/AIDS and Ebola epidemics, I attempt to show that the marginalization of Africa in medical research and medical research ethics is deliberate rather than accidental. It is causally related, in general terms, to a Eurocentric hegemony derived from colonialism and colonial indoctrination cum proselytization. I end by proposing seven theses for the critical reflection and appraisal of the reader. 相似文献
19.
Herkert JR 《Science and engineering ethics》2001,7(3):403-414
Three frames of reference for engineering ethics are discussed—individual, professional and social—which can be further broken
down into “microethics” concerned with individuals and the internal relations of the engineering profession and “macroethics”
referring to the collective social responsibility of the engineering profession and to societal decisions about technology.
Few attempts have been made at integrating microethical and macroethical approaches to engineering ethics. The approach suggested
here is to focus on the role of professional engineering societies in linking individual and professional ethics and in linking
professional and social ethics. A research program is outlined using ethics support as an example of the former, and the issuance
of position statements on product liability as an example of the latter.
An earlier version of this paper was presented at the International Symposium on Technology and Society 2000 (ISTAS 2000),
Rome, Italy, 7 September 2000.
Joseph R. Herkert directs a dual-degree program in engineering and humanities/social sciences and is editor of Social, Ethical, and Policy Implications of Engineering (Wiley/IEEE Press). 相似文献
20.
Davis M 《Science and engineering ethics》2001,7(3):379-390
This paper argues that research for engineering ethics should routinely involve philosophers, social scientists, and engineers, and should focus for now on certain basic questions such as: Who is an engineer? What is engineering? What do engineers do? How do they make decisions? And how much control do they actually have over what they do? 相似文献