共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
2.
Warren Shrader 《Philosophical Studies》2010,150(2):285-300
Sydney Shoemaker has recently given an account of emergent properties according to which emergent properties are a special
type of structural property and the determination relation holding between emergent properties and their base properties is
one of “mere nomological supervenience.” According to Shoemaker, emergent properties are what he calls type-2 microstructural
properties, whereas physical properties are type-1 microstructural properties. After highlighting the advantages of viewing
emergent properties as a special class of microstructural properties, I show how according to his own causal theory of properties
type-2 microstructural properties actually reduce to type-1 microstructural properties, and thus do not truly count as emergent.
I then suggest an alternative view according to which emergent properties are actually a third type of microstructural property,
one not considered by Shoemaker. I conclude with reflections why we might view the dependence relation between emergent properties
and their physical base properties as a causal relation rather than one of mere supervenience. 相似文献
3.
4.
David Phillips 《Ethical Theory and Moral Practice》2007,10(5):457-468
I argue that John Mackie’s treatment of practical reason is both attractive and unjustly neglected. In particular, I argue
that it is importantly different from, and much more plausible than, the kind of instrumentalist approach famously articulated
by Bernard Williams. This matters for the interpretation of the arguments for Mackie’s most famous thesis: moral scepticism,
the claim that there are no objective values. Richard Joyce has recently defended a version or variant of moral scepticism
by invoking an instrumentalist theory like Williams’. I argue that this is a serious strategic mistake.
相似文献
David PhillipsEmail: |
5.
Brad Thompson 《Philosophical Studies》2007,135(3):307-334
Sydney Shoemaker has given a sophisticated theory of phenomenal content, motivated by the transparency of experience and by
the possibility of spectrum inversion without illusion (1994, 2000, 2001, 2002). It centers on the idea that color experiences
represent what he calls “appearance properties”. I consider the different sorts of appearance properties that Shoemaker has
suggested might enter into phenomenal content – occurrent appearance properties, dispositional appearance properties, and
higher-order dispositional appearance properties – and argue that none of them are plausibly represented by color experiences.
I argue that Shoemaker's theory faces a dilemma – either it makes misperception too difficult, or it does not truly accommodate
veridical spectrum inversion. I then examine some alternative Russellian theories of phenomenal content that might be consistent
with Shoemaker's motivations, including a different sort of proposal recently suggested by Shoemaker (forthcoming). I argue
that these views are also lacking, for similar reasons as the appearance property view. Finally, I conclude that in order
for a representationalist theory to properly accommodate spectrum inversion without illusion, phenomenal content must include
an indexical element. Such a view requires the adoption of a broadly Fregean theory of phenomenal content, according to which
sameness of phenomenal character does not entail sameness in extension. What phenomenally identical experiences have in common
is not what they represent, but how they represent. 相似文献
6.
7.
Lars Bo Gundersen 《The Philosophical quarterly》2000,50(199):227-229
In The Philosophical Quarterly , 48 (1998), Alexander Bird raises an objection against the conditional analysis of dispositions: where an 'antidote' is present all the supposed conditions for manifestation of a disposition are fulfilled but the manifestation does not occur. But Bird's argument suffers from equivocation. If we spell out properly whether the disposition's conditions are to include the presence of the antidote or not, the apparent counter-examples disappear. So his examples do not undermine the conditional analysis of dispositions; they show merely that we need to be careful about describing the examples consistently. 相似文献
8.
Appeals to dispositionality in explanations of phenomena in metaphysics and the philosophy of mind, require that we first agree on what we are talking about. I sketch an account of what dispositionality might be. That account will place me at odds with most current conceptions of dispositionality. My aim is not to establish a weighty ontological thesis, however, but to move the discussion ahead in two respects. First, I want to call attention to the extent to which assumptions philosophers have made about dispositionality are far from innocent. The assumptions incorporate substantive theses that, by constraining the space of acceptable answers to particular philosophical questions, have inhibited the search for answers to those questions. Second, and more positively, I hope to open up the space of possibilities by offering an alternative way of conceiving dispositionality developed by C. B. Martin.This paper was written for a conference on Dispositions and Laws of Nature held at the University of Alabama, Birmingham, 7–8 February 2003; Michael Watkins commented. I have benefited from those comments, from remarks by other participants, and from discussions with David Armstrong and my colleague, David Robb, on the topic. The account sketched here is based on C. B. Martins work on dispositions. See Martin (1992, 1993, 1994, 1997), Martin and Heil (1999), and Martins contribution to Armstrong et al. (1996). The position is developed in detail in Heil (2003). 相似文献
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
Denny Bradshaw 《The Southern journal of philosophy》2003,41(2):169-182
14.
Jesse R. Steinberg 《Philosophical Studies》2010,148(3):323-341
It is generally agreed that dispositions cannot be analyzed in terms of simple subjunctive conditionals (because of what are
called “masked dispositions” and “finkish dispositions”). I here defend a qualified subjunctive account of dispositions according
to which an object is disposed to Φ when conditions C obtain if and only if, if conditions C were to obtain, then the object
would Φ ceteris paribus. I argue that this account does not fall prey to the objections that have been raised in the literature. 相似文献
15.
Dispositions and Antidotes 总被引:8,自引:0,他引:8
Alexander Bird 《The Philosophical quarterly》1998,48(191):227-234
C.B. Martin has shown that the simple conditional analysis of disposition concepts (x is disposed at time t to give response r to stimulus s) is in error. This is due to finkish dispositions which are caused to disappear by the stimulus s. David Lewis has proposed an improved analysis which takes account of finkish dispositions by requiring that the appropriate causal basis remains for a sufficiently long time. I argue that Lewis' analysis also fails, because of the existence of antidotes. An antidote to a disposition interferes with its normal operation so that the stimulus does not bring about the usual response. I consider several possible defences of Lewis' analysis and a plausible repair, but find these unsatisfactory. I conclude by suggesting that an analysis of disposition concepts is not available because an unavoidable indexical element (e.g., reference to normal circumstances) is present in explanations of these concepts. In this regard they may be thought of as akin to theoretical or natural kind concepts. 相似文献
16.
17.
Gabriele Contessa 《Philosophical Studies》2013,162(2):401-419
In this paper I argue that olfactory experience, like visual experience, is exteroceptive: it seems to one that odours, when one smells them, are external to the body, as it seems to one that objects are external to the body when one sees them. Where the sense of smell has been discussed by philosophers, it has often been supposed to be non-exteroceptive. The strangeness of this philosophical orthodoxy makes it natural to ask what would lead to its widespread acceptance. I argue that philosophers have been misled by a visuocentric model of what exteroceptivity involves. Since olfaction lacks the spatial features that make vision exteroceptive the conclusion that olfaction is nonexteroceptive can appear quite compelling, particularly in the absence of an alternative model of exteroceptivity appropriate to olfaction. I offer a model according to which odours seem to be external to the body because they seem to be brought into the nose from without by sniffing and breathing through the nostrils. I argue that some natural-seeming objections to this model rely on substantive assumptions about how the senses are distinguished from one another, and how perceptual experience is put together out of its modality-specific parts, that require defence. 相似文献
18.
SUNGHO CHOI 《Philosophy and phenomenological research》2009,78(3):568-590
The idea that dispositions are an intrinsic matter has been popular among contemporary philosophers of dispositions. In this paper I will first state this idea as exactly as possible. I will then examine whether it poses any threat to the two current versions of the conditional analysis of dispositions, namely, the simple and reformed conditional analysis of dispositions. The upshot is that the intrinsic nature of dispositions, when properly understood, doesn't spell trouble for either of the two versions of the conditional analysis of dispositions. Along the way, I will propose an extensionally correct and practically useful criterion for identifying nomically intrinsic dispositions and criticize one objection raised by Lewis against the simple conditional analysis of dispositions. 相似文献
19.
20.