共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
2.
3.
Referential/attributive: A contextualist proposal 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
Francois Recanati 《Philosophical Studies》1989,56(3):217-249
4.
5.
Jaakko Hintikka 《Argumentation》1987,1(3):211-238
Several of the so-called fallacies in Aristotle are not in fact mistaken inference-types, but mistakes or breaches of rules in the questioning games which were practiced in the Academy and in the Lyceum. Hence the entire Aristotelian theory of fallacies ought to be studied by reference to the author's interrogative model of inquiry, based on his theory of questions and answers, rather than as a part of the theory of inference. Most of the fallacies mentioned by Aristotle can in fact be diagnosed by means of the interrogative model, including petitio principii, multiple questions, babbling, etc., and so can Aristotle's alleged anticipation of the fallacy of argumentum ad hominem. The entire Aristotelian conception of inquiry is an interrogative one. Deductive conclusions caught Aristotle's attention in the form of answers that every rational interlocutor must give, assuming only his own earlier answers. Several features of Aristotle's methodology can be understood by means of the interrogative model, including the role of endoxa in it. Theoretically, there is also considerable leeway as to whether fallacies are conceived of as mistakes in questioning or as breaches of the rules that govern questioning games. 相似文献
6.
7.
Douglas Walton 《Synthese》2011,179(3):377-407
This paper argues that some traditional fallacies should be considered as reasonable arguments when used as part of a properly
conducted dialog. It is shown that argumentation schemes, formal dialog models, and profiles of dialog are useful tools for
studying properties of defeasible reasoning and fallacies. It is explained how defeasible reasoning of the most common sort
can deteriorate into fallacious argumentation in some instances. Conditions are formulated that can be used as normative tools
to judge whether a given defeasible argument is fallacious or not. It is shown that three leading violations of proper dialog
standards for defeasible reasoning necessary to see how fallacies work are: (a) improper failure to retract a commitment,
(b) failure of openness to defeat, and (c) illicit reversal of burden of proof. 相似文献
8.
Luciano Floridi 《Synthese》2009,167(2):317-325
The paper argues that the two best known formal logical fallacies, namely denying the antecedent (DA) and affirming the consequent
(AC) are not just basic and simple errors, which prove human irrationality, but rather informational shortcuts, which may
provide a quick and dirty way of extracting useful information from the environment. DA and AC are shown to be degraded versions
of Bayes’ theorem, once this is stripped of some of its probabilities. The less the probabilities count, the closer these
fallacies become to a reasoning that is not only informationally useful but also logically valid. 相似文献
9.
Maya Bar-Hillel 《Acta psychologica》1984,55(2):91-107
Representativeness is the name given to the heuristic people often employ when they judge the probability of a sample by how well it represents certain salient features of the population from which it was drawn. The representativeness heuristic has also been used to account for how people judge the probability that a given population is the source of some sample. The latter probability, however, depends on other factors (e.g., the population's prior probability) as well as on the sample characteristics. A review of existing evidence suggests that the ignoring of such factors, a central finding of the heuristics approach to judgment under uncertainty, is a phenomenon which is conceptually distinct from the representativeness heuristic. These factors (base rates, sample size, and predictability) do not always exert the proper influence on people's first-order probability judgments, but they are not ignored when people make second-order (i.e., confidence) judgments. Other fallacies and biases in subjective evaluations of probability are, however, direct causal results of the employment of representativeness. For example, representativeness may be applied to the wrong features. Most devastating, perhaps, is that subjective probability judgments obey a logic of representativeness judgments, even though probability ought to obey an altogether different logic. Yet although the role of representativeness judgments in probability estimation leaves a lot to be desired, it is hard to envision prediction and inference completely unaided by representativeness. 相似文献
10.
Jonathan E. Adler 《Argumentation》1993,7(3):263-272
An epistemic account of fallacies is one which takes it as a necessary condition for a fallacy that it has a tendency to produce false or unwarranted beliefs. The most sophisticated form of this account occurs in an article by Robert J. Fogelin and Timothy J. Duggan (Fallacies,Argumentation 1, 1987, pp. 255–262). I criticize the Fogelin and Duggan proposal, in particular, and epistemic accounts, more generally. Though an epistemic approach is attractive, it enlarges the class of fallacies, beyond what would be permitted by traditional accounts. I also question thenecessity of fallacies leading to unwarranted beliefs. Some fallacies are fallacious due to their expected harm to argument practices. This position touches on a theme in the work of Van Eemeren and Grootendorst, though I criticize their notion of rules of argument as too broad. 相似文献
11.
12.
Robert L. Thorndike 《Psychometrika》1942,7(2):85-102
This paper is concerned particularly with certain regression effects which appear whenever matched groups are drawn from populations which differ with regard to the characteristics being studied. It is shown that regression will produce systematic differences between specifically matched. The size and direction of these differences depends upon the differences between the parent populations both in the matching and in the experimental variables and upon the correlation between the matching and experimental variables. Formulas are presented for estimating the expected regression effect. Several alternative procedures are suggested for avoiding the erroneous conclusions which the regression effect is likely to suggest. 相似文献
13.
14.
15.
Being unreasonable: Perelman and the problem of fallacies 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
James Crosswhite 《Argumentation》1993,7(4):385-402
Most work on fallacies continues to conceptualize fallacious reasoning as involving a breach of a formal or quasi-formal rule. Chaim Perelman's theory of argumentation provides a way to conceptualize fallacies in a completely different way. His approach depends on an understanding of standards of rationality as essentially connected with conceptions of universality. Such an approach allows one to get beyond some of the basic problems of fallacy theory, and turns informal logic toward substantive philosophical questions. I show this by reinterpreting three so-called fallacies - theargumentum ad baculum, equivocation and composition/division - in the light of Perelman's account. 相似文献
16.
17.
18.
19.
A constellation of joint probability estimates is semantically coherent when the quantitative relationship among estimates
of P(A), P(B), P(A and B), and P(A or B) is consistent with the relationship among the sets described in the problem statement.
The possible probability estimates can form an extremely large number of permutations. However, this entire problem space
can be reduced to six theoretically meaningful patterns: logically fallacious (conjunction or disjunction fallacies), identical
sets (e.g., water and H2O), mutually exclusive sets (e.g., horses and zebras), subsets (e.g., robins and birds), overlapping sets (e.g., accountants
and musicians), and inconsistent overlapping sets. Determining which of these patterns describes any set of probability estimates
has been automated using Excel spreadsheet formulae. Researchers may use the semantic coherence technique to examine the consequences
of differently worded problems, individual differences, or experimental manipulations. The spreadsheet described above can
be downloaded as a supplement from http://brm.psychonomic-journals.org/content/supplemental. 相似文献
20.
Functional neuroanatomy of cognitive processes is generally derived by subtraction of a control task from an experimental task. We show that this method is logically untenable and propose to replace it with an adaptation of the specific-effect method and of the additive-factor method. The basic flaw that undermines the subtractive method is the comparison between different tasks. We argue that the specific-effect method should be used when investigating activations produced by different levels of a qualitative variable, whereas the additive-factor method should be used for quantitative variables. The use of these methods allows one to distinguish between parallel and serial stages of processing and between local and distributed processing. 相似文献