共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
2.
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion - 相似文献
3.
Patrick Horn 《International Journal for Philosophy of Religion》2012,71(1):39-53
D. Z. Phillips is widely assumed to have held that Christian immortality has no reality outside of language. The author challenges
that assumption, demonstrating that Phillips wished to show that contemporary analytic philosophy distorts the reality that
immortality has for believers. While most philosophical accounts of Christian immortality depend upon terms that have little
religious significance, Phillips offered accounts that stress the centrality of that significance. The author gives an account
of the sort of philosophical attention that Phillips gave to Christian immortality and demonstrates Phillips’ lament for both
the lack of this sort of attention in contemporary philosophy as well as the loss of certain ways of living that exemplify
a belief in eternal life with God. 相似文献
4.
5.
6.
John H. Whittaker 《International Journal for Philosophy of Religion》2008,63(1-3):103-129
As an illustration of what Phillips called the “heterogeneity of sense,” this essay concentrates on differences in what is
meant by a “reason for belief.” Sometimes saying that a belief is reasonable simply commends the belief’s unquestioned acceptance
as a part of what we understand as a sensible outlook. Here the standard picture of justifying truth claims on evidential
grounds breaks down; and it also breaks down in cases of fundamental moral and religious disagreement, where the basic beliefs
that we hold affect our conception of what counts as a reliable ground of judgment. Phillips accepts the resultant variations
in our conceptions of rational judgment as a part of logic, just as Wittgenstein did. All objective means of determining the truth or falsity of an assertion presume some underlying conceptual agreement about what counts
as good judgment. This means that the possibility of objective justification is limited. But no pernicious relativism results
from this view, for as Wittgenstein said, “After reason comes persuasion.” There is, moreover, a non-objective criterion of
sorts in the moral and religious requirement that one be able to live with one’s commitments. In such cases, good judgment
is still possible, but it differs markedly from the standard model of making rational inferences. 相似文献
7.
8.
9.
Brian Davies 《Philosophical Investigations》2007,30(3):219-244
In this paper I try briefly to say why I think that what D.Z. Phillips had to say about belief in God can be defended against certain familiar criticisms, and why I think that his treatment could have been improved. I note passages in his writings which might be thought not to reflect what belief in God amounts to, but I argue that these passages can be read as reflecting belief in God as we find it in biblical authors and in writers like Thomas Aquinas. Having noted that Phillips rejects attempts to do natural theology on largely Humean grounds, I argue against these grounds as echoed by Phillips and draw attention to a tradition of natural theology not subject to Humean objections, a tradition to which Phillips might have paid more attention than he did. 相似文献
10.
William J. Wainwright 《Topoi》1995,14(2):87-93
Section I argues that theistic religions incorporate metaphysical systems and that these systems are explanatory. Section II defends these claims against D. Z. Phillips's objections to the epistemic realism and correspondence theory of truth which they imply. I conclude by raising questions about the status of Phillips's own project. 相似文献
11.
12.
13.
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion - 相似文献
14.
15.
16.
17.
Stephen Mulhall 《Philosophical Investigations》2007,30(3):266-284
This paper critically examines D. Z. Phillips’ critical examination of Nagel's and Williams's famous exchange about moral luck. It argues that Phillips fails properly to identify the fundamental issues at stake in the exchange – particularly with respect to the role of scepticism, of the picture of the will as an extensionless point, and of the putative supremacy of morality – and so fails to recognise a certain commonality of interest between himself and those he criticises. 相似文献
18.
19.
《Journal of personality assessment》2013,95(1):171-173
Psychometric characteristics of the Social Introversion (Si) scale, the Social Discomfort (SOD) scale, and the Si subscales of the MMPI-2 were examined in clinical samples of 122 psychiatric patients and 399 patients with substance-use disorders, The combined Si[sub 1] (Shyness/Self-Consciousness) and Si[sub 2] Social Avoidance) subscales correlated highly with SOD and are apparent measures of the social introversion construct. Si[sub 3] (Self/Other Alienation) was found to be a measure of the general maladjustment factor of the MMPI-2. Content not included on the Si subscales was divided into a group of items that measures general maladjustment and 2 other item groups that may assess minor constructs related to social introversion. As in previous research, the 3 Si subscales accounted well for variance in Si scores. 相似文献
20.
Richard Amesbury 《Philosophical Investigations》2007,30(3):201-218
D. Z. Phillips’ work in philosophy was animated by his interest in the diversity and heterogeneity of moral and religious perspectives and his antipathy towards philosophical theories that afford this variety little or no conceptual space. In contrast to what he perceived as essentialist efforts to promote certain viewpoints and to disparage others, Phillips championed a “contemplative conception” of philosophy, according to which the philosopher's aim is neither to underwrite nor to undermine but to understand. This paper argues that philosophy, while disinterested in its aims, nevertheless derives its elucidatory force from the normative contexts within which it is practised and read. 相似文献