首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
《Synthese》1948,7(1):457-457
  相似文献   

2.
Phillipp Frank 《Synthese》1948,7(1):458-465
  相似文献   

3.
逻辑经验主义对实验心理学的关注并非只是由于其结果的作用或其态度上的相似性,而且由于(或许是更为重要的)对澄清其概念的共同需要。逻辑经验主义对物理概念的分析是一种哲学成就的范式,而他们在心理学中同样的分析工作也被看做是规范科学的疑难解决方案。在这种范式的背后隐藏着统一科学的哲学理想。围绕经验问题,逻辑经验主义与心理学之间在20世纪30年代出现了大量互动;正是根据这个问题,以及在逻辑经验主义对统一科学的强调的关联中,我们才能很好地理解逻辑经验主义的心理学哲学及其对心理学的影响。以卡尔纳普、费格尔和托曼为最初代表,他们提出完全不同的处理方式,把心理学看做经验科学,就可以得到其他科学同样具有的主体间性,因此,这就使得逻辑经验主义获得了它希望得到的地位。  相似文献   

4.
与经验主义或实证主义之前的形式相比,逻辑和数学哲学是最具逻辑经验主义特征的。逻辑经验主义不仅因此得名,而且也为科学经验主义的成功点燃了希望。然而,经验主义者的心理主义与实证主义者的逻辑主义对数学本质的探讨始终不能达成共识。基于这种背景,维特根斯坦《逻辑哲学论》的发表对于维也纳小组的影响深远、意义重大。逻辑经验主义在20世纪20年代的数学哲学都是植根于《逻辑哲学论》的。本文在第一部分阐释了它何以成为该学派在"哲学上的转折点"。而维也纳学派从一开始就试图对《逻辑哲学论》进行革新,使之服务于其本身的纲领。本文在第二部分着重探讨了他们关于这些问题所展开的激烈讨论。这种状况一直持续到1931年卡尔纳普提出了"句法"纲领,该纲领从根本上超越了逻辑经验主义的原有框架。但由于当时欧洲逻辑经验主义者受到纳粹的迫害而四分五散,"句法"观点并未受到广泛关注。本文在第三、第四部分具体分析了逻辑经验主义如何由《逻辑哲学论》向"句法"思想转变的过程。  相似文献   

5.
行为主义心理学、组织社会学长期以来是人类行为研究的理论基础 ,它们不仅深刻地影响到人们对行为的实质、组织的结构、理论与实践的关系等广泛问题的理解 ,而且还影响到对诸如领导、组织设计、行政培训等具体问题的认识。西方教育管理理论和实践的典型特征是行为科学的方法 ,这种特征的背后是逻辑经验主义的方法论[1 ] ,它提供了大量的“客观的”、综合的关于行为研究人员和实践者在各自领域里行使职能的观点。由于学校作为一种组织类型 ,其行为具有典型性 ,因此 ,许多行为主义者通过行为的比较教育研究 ,揭示人类行为的内在本质 ,从而控制…  相似文献   

6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
Despite the emergence of new forms of feminist empiricism, there continues to be resistance to the idea that feminist political commitment can be integral to hypothesis testing in science when that process adheres strictly to empiricist norms and is grounded in a realist conception of objectivity. I explore the virtues of such feminist empiricism, arguing that the resistance is, in large part, due to the lingering effects of positivism.  相似文献   

11.
12.
I argue that Nelson's feminist transformation of empiricism provides the basis of a dialogue across three currently competing feminist epistemologies: feminist empiricism, feminist standpoint theories, and postmodern feminism, a dialogue that will result in a dissolution of the apparent tensions between these epistemologies and provide an epistemology with the openness and fluidity needed to embrace the concerns of feminists.  相似文献   

13.
There is a principle that both generates and destroys empiricism. It is a plausible principle, thus often appealed to. (Bernard Williams and Michael Dummett are notable subscribers.) Its consequences prove it wrong. This is a story of empiricism's rise and fall (a fall Frege mapped out for it). It is historically sketchy. But one should focus on the principle.  相似文献   

14.
15.
16.
17.
This paper suggests that one single thread characterizes the developments of French phenomenology that occurred after 1990 in the wake of Merleau-Ponty's and Levinas's major contributions. Janicaud in 1991 had already identified one global trend in French phenomenology and believed it was possible to unite the thoughts of Levinas, Henry, Marion and Chrétien under the common banner of “theological phenomenology.” However, his analysis seems to fail to account for deeper-seated affinities that exist between French phenomenologists such as Marion, Lacoste, Chrétien, Richir, Depraz, Romano – and Benoist for part of his work. This is the reason why, although the present paper does agree with Janicaud's idea that the French authors who define themselves as phenomenologists share some common ground, it defines this common trend quite differently, i.e., as a form of epistemological realism that ultimately manifests itself as a radical empiricism.

Consequently, the present study will state and defend three hypotheses: (1) contemporary French phenomenology professes a form of realism of experience, which is the true rallying point (space of exchange) of otherwise differing elaborations; (2) this type of epistemological empiricism, by virtue of its radicality, implies a problem that threatens to drive phenomenology towards its own dissolution, because as it precipitates in fine the dilution of philosophical discourse into a multitude of other discourses; (3) this variant of empiricism shows that, within its strictly defined viewpoint, there is scarcely any difference between French phenomenology and a certain part of French analytical philosophy. All three hypotheses lead to the same conclusion: the determination of the defining aspect of contemporary French phenomenology entails, beyond the apparent, misleading, and futile quarrel of paradigms, to bring to light a common space for contemporary French philosophy, which, from both perspectives, can be conveyed by the single term “to show.” It is, in fact, the elevation of “to show” to the detriment of “to demonstrate” that seems to ensnare thinkers within an impasse.  相似文献   


18.
19.
Mark Colyvan 《Erkenntnis》1999,51(2-3):323-332
The Quine-Putnam indispensability argument urges us to place mathematical entities on the same ontological footing as (other) theoretical entities of empirical science. Recently this argument has attracted much criticism, and in this paper I address one criticism due to Elliott Sober. Sober argues that mathematical theories cannot share the empirical support accrued by our best scientific theories, since mathematical propositions are not being tested in the same way as the clearly empirical propositions of science. In this paper I defend the Quine-Putnam argument against Sober's objections. This revised version was published online in July 2006 with corrections to the Cover Date.  相似文献   

20.
Walzer  Michael 《Philosophia》2020,48(4):1291-1297
Philosophia - This article is a defense of the Nuremberg Trials. It addresses the standard criticism of the trials and outlines six principles of international law that constitute the legacy of...  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号