共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
2.
3.
4.
Giora Hon 《国际科学哲学研究》1991,5(3):257-268
One cannot discount experimental errors and turn the attention to the logicomathematical structure of a physical theory without distorting the nature of the scientific method. The occurrence of errors in experiments constitutes an inherent feature of the attempt to test theories in the physical world. This feature deserves proper attention which has been neglected. An attempt is made to address this problem. 相似文献
5.
Igor Douven 《Synthese》2009,168(1):23-52
External world skeptics are typically opposed to admitting as evidence anything that goes beyond the purely phenomenal, and
equally typically, they disown the use of rules of inference that might enable one to move from premises about the phenomenal
alone to a conclusion about the external world. This seems to bar any a posteriori resolution of the skepticism debate. This
paper argues that the situation is not quite so hopeless, and that an a posteriori resolution of the debate becomes possible
once it is recognized that the skeptic holds overly defensive and ill-motivated positions vis-à-vis both evidence and inference,
and that more reasonable ones are available. In stating these more reasonable positions, as well as in showing how they make
possible an a posteriori resolution of the skepticism debate, the paper draws on the machinery of Bayesian epistemology. 相似文献
6.
7.
8.
McGuire J 《Behavioral sciences & the law》2000,18(4):413-426
This paper addresses the question of whether criminal law, especially in its sentencing and penological aspects, can be adjusted in its workings to incorporate the perspective of therapeutic jurisprudence. A conceptual framework developed by Wexler, Winick, and their colleagues is employed to provide a basis for reflection on the operation and impact of sentencing processes. Of considerable importance in this exercise is a mounting volume of evidence concerning the outcomes of work with adjudicated offenders, which illustrates the potential of psycho-educational, behavioral-cognitive skills-training, and therapeutic programs for reduction of recidivism. Such intervention programs are currently offered within the limits set by, but are not intrinsic components of, judicial decisions. The psycho-legal implications of these findings are discussed and some possibilities surveyed for tentative exploration of actively therapeutic departures within crimino-legal decision-making. 相似文献
9.
W A Tiller M J Kohane W E Dibble 《Integrative Physiological and Behavioral Science》2000,35(2):142-62; discussion 163
Although quantum mechanics allows consciousness to have some effect on the collapse of wave functions, most conventional scientists expect the effect to be quite small. Their experience with expert systems, computer-aided design, etc., would cause them to deny the possibility that a specific human intention could be imprinted into a simple electronic device via a meditative process and that this device could then influence a target experiment in accordance with the specific intention. Here, via two very different target experiments, that prevailing supposition has been experimentally tested and found to be fallacious! For each target experiment, one starts with two identical physical devices, isolates them from each other and "charges" one with the specific intention for the particular experiment. This charging process involved the services of four highly qualified meditators to imprint the device with the specific intention. The devices were then wrapped in aluminum foil and separately shipped, via Federal Express approximately 2,000 miles to a laboratory where the actual target experiments were conducted by others. For the two experiments, the intentions were (1) to decrease (increase) the pH of water by one pH unit and (2) to increase the ATP/ADP ratio in fruit fly larvae so as to significantly decrease their development time. For (1), changes of 0.5 to 1.0 pH units were achieved while, for (2), reductions of approximately 15 percent in larval development time for the imprinted vs. unimprinted device were observed (p<0.005). From a theoretical perspective, (1) a thermodynamic basis is provided for the effect of intention on both the electrochemical potential and flux of molecular species, (2) a conceptual model for linking subtle domains with the physical domain devices is given, and (3) a conceptual model is also given of how such devices may broadcast specific prime directive information via intention-augmented electromagnetism which can "tilt" chemical reactions in appropriate ways within the target experiment. 相似文献
10.
William A. Tiller Michael J. Kohane Walter E. Dibble 《Integrative psychological & behavioral science》2000,35(2):142-161
Although quantum mechanics allows consciousness to have some effect on the collapse of wave functions, most conventional scientists
expect the effect to be quite small. Their experience with expert systems, computer-aided design, etc., would cause them to
deny the possibility that a specific human intention could be imprinted into a simple electronic device via a meditative process
and that this device could then influence a target experiment in accordance with the specific intention. Here, via two very
different target experiments, that prevailing supposition has been experimentally tested and found to be fallacious!
For each target experiment, one starts with two identical physical devices, isolates them from each other and “charges” one
with the specific intention for the particular experiment. This charging process involved the services of four highly qualified
meditators to imprint the device with the specific intention. The devices were then wrapped in aluminum foil and separately
shipped, via Federal Express ∼2,000 miles to a laboratory where the actual target experiments were conducted by others.
For the two experiments, the intentions were (1) to decrease (increase) the pH of water by one pH unit and (2) to increase
the ATP/ADP ratio in fruit fly larvae so as to significantly decrease their development time. For (1), changes of 0.5 to 1.0
pH units were achieved while, for (2), reductions of ∼15 percent in larval development time for the imprinted vs. unimprinted
device were observed (p<0.005).
From a theoretical perspective, (1) a thermodynamic basis is provided for the effect of intention on both the electrochemical
potential and flux of molecular species, (2) a conceptual model for linking subtle domains with the physical domain devices
is given, and (3) a conceptual model is also given of how such devices may broadcast specific prime directive information
via intention—augmented electromagnetism which can “tilt” chemical reactions in appropriate ways within the target experiment. 相似文献
11.
Beebe J 《The Journal of analytical psychology》2004,49(2):177-191
Science means not just 'knowing', but knowing verified by replicability. Science is particularly hard to bring to depth psychology because the individual uniquenesses that can't be repeated are what make people most deeply themselves. Everyone, including the analytic investigator, however, has a science, in the sense of a world-view that is replicated by experience. Jung offered hermeneutics as an alternative mode to science for getting to know the psychological subject. But as Heidegger emphasized, hermeneutics always begins with the projection of a world-view, i.e., the science of the would-be interpreter. In the analytic situation, dialogue is available to test the world-view and enlarge its horizon, in accord with Gadamer's expansion of hermeneutics, 'the classical discipline concerned with the art of understanding texts', into a method of inquiry open to the possibilities of otherness. An example is given from an analytic training seminar, in which the author began by projecting his version of the theory of psychological types onto the dream material a candidate offered in response to the seminar. A dialogue with the candidate ensued which enabled the teacher to correct his original, somewhat rigid, application of his scientific viewpoint. In such a dialogue, psyche emerges as the final interpreter of what is, generating hypotheses that can fruitfully be applied to the understanding of other cases. 相似文献
12.
Collisions between trains and pedestrians continue to be the most likely accident to result in severe injuries and fatalities on the rail network. While a range of countermeasures have been utilised in an attempt to reduce the incidence of risky behaviours at level crossings, limited focus has been directed towards deterrence-based approaches to improve crossing safety. As a result, this study explored pedestrians’ perceptions of legal and non-legal sanctions at level crossings, with particular emphasis directed towards identifying factors that maximise perceptual deterrence and reduce the occurrence of rule violations. In total, 636 individuals volunteered to participate in the study that required completion of either an online or paper version of a questionnaire that focused on behaviours and perceptions. Participants were more likely to report intentionally violating level crossing rules (24.52%, n = 156) compared to making crossing errors (3.46%, n = 22). Knowledge of the possibility of sanctions (e.g., monetary fines) was low. The threat of being injured and feeling shame when breaching crossing rules were the highest reported perceptual deterrent factors, higher even than the certainty and severity of sanctions. Regression analysis revealed that males who had lower perceptions of certainty of apprehension and displayed a tendency to repeat the behaviour were most likely to deliberately break crossing rules. However, this group also recognised the physical risks of violating rules and that it breached social norms. In regards to identifying effective countermeasures, increasing police presence was considered the most effective approach to reduce violations, which is directly linked to deterrence processes such as increasing perceptual certainty. This paper will further outline the study findings in regards to perceptual deterrence-based research as well as provide direction for future research efforts to develop effective countermeasures designed to improve pedestrian safety. 相似文献
13.
Tom Rockmore 《Metaphilosophy》1997,28(4):302-313
There is a difference between internationalism in politics and philosophy. This paper takes the position that internationalism is possible in politics but not in philosophy, although it is an objective worth pursuing in both domains. 相似文献
14.
Rob Van Someren Greve 《Philosophia》2012,40(2):411-414
The characterization of objective, normative reasons to φ as facts (or truths) that count in favor of φ-ing is widely accepted. But are there any further conditions that considerations which count in favor of φ-ing must meet, in order to count as a reason to φ? In this brief paper, I consider and reject one such condition, recently proposed by Caspar Hare. 相似文献
15.
16.
17.
Neal Jahren 《Synthese》1990,82(3):309-328
The author defends John R. Searle's Chinese Room argument against a particular objection made by William J. Rapaport called the Korean Room. Foundational issues such as the relationship of strong AI to human mentality and the adequacy of the Turing Test are discussed. Through undertaking a Gedankenexperiment similar to Searle's but which meets new specifications given by Rapaport for an AI system, the author argues that Rapaport's objection to Searle does not stand and that Rapaport's arguments seem convincing only because they assume the foundations of strong AI at the outset.The author wishes to thank Brad Bergeron, David J. Cole, James H. Fetzer, Charles E. Jahren, Michael Losonsky, William J. Rapaport, and Robyn Roslak for reading earlier drafts of this paper and/or their general discussions on cognitive science and AI. An earlier version of this paper was given at the Student Conference of the Minnesota Philosophical Society, Bethel College, 1988. 相似文献
18.
19.
20.