全文获取类型
收费全文 | 1185篇 |
免费 | 51篇 |
国内免费 | 3篇 |
专业分类
1239篇 |
出版年
2025年 | 1篇 |
2024年 | 17篇 |
2023年 | 39篇 |
2022年 | 10篇 |
2021年 | 12篇 |
2020年 | 51篇 |
2019年 | 58篇 |
2018年 | 47篇 |
2017年 | 61篇 |
2016年 | 56篇 |
2015年 | 41篇 |
2014年 | 48篇 |
2013年 | 135篇 |
2012年 | 28篇 |
2011年 | 21篇 |
2010年 | 19篇 |
2009年 | 34篇 |
2008年 | 68篇 |
2007年 | 78篇 |
2006年 | 76篇 |
2005年 | 49篇 |
2004年 | 44篇 |
2003年 | 25篇 |
2002年 | 37篇 |
2001年 | 22篇 |
2000年 | 37篇 |
1999年 | 22篇 |
1998年 | 17篇 |
1997年 | 27篇 |
1996年 | 10篇 |
1995年 | 4篇 |
1994年 | 9篇 |
1993年 | 5篇 |
1992年 | 7篇 |
1991年 | 6篇 |
1990年 | 7篇 |
1989年 | 2篇 |
1988年 | 8篇 |
1987年 | 1篇 |
排序方式: 共有1239条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
101.
Robert J. Howell 《Philosophical Studies》2007,135(2):145-177
In this paper I argue that Frank Jackson’s Knowledge Argument is better considered not as an argument against physicalism,
but as an argument that objective theories must be incomplete. I argue that despite the apparent diversity of responses to
the knowledge argument, they all boil down to a response according to which genuine epistemic gains are made when an individual
has an experience. I call this the acquaintance response. I then argue that this response violates an intuitive stricture
on the objectivity of theories. Therefore, the knowledge argument does show that objective theories cannot provide a complete
understanding of the world. The result, however, is that both objective dualism and objective physicalism are refuted by the
argument. In the end it is suggested that the notion of “subjective physicalism” is one that should be pursued. 相似文献
102.
Yuanguo He 《Frontiers of Philosophy in China》2007,2(2):291-307
Before and during the times of Confucius and Aristotle, the concept of friendship had very different implications. This paper
compares Confucius’ with Aristotle’s thoughts on friendship from two perspectives: xin 信 (fidelity, faithfulness) and le 乐 (joy). The Analects emphasizes the xin as the basis of friendship. Aristotle holds that there are three kinds of friends and corresponding to them are three types
of friendship. In the friendship for the sake of pleasure, there is no xin; in the legal form of friendship for the sake of utility, xin is guaranteed by law; and in the moral form of friendship for the sake of utility, xin is guaranteed by morality; in the friendship for the sake of virtue, xin is an indispensable part. Both thinkers believe friends can bring joy to human life. According to Confucius, it is the joy
of rendao 仁道 (benevolence), whereas for Aristotle, it is the joy of Reason. There are many commonalities and differences between the
two. The commonalities reveal some inner links between Confucian rendao and Aristotelian Reason. It seems that the differences between rendao and Reason are the differences between moral reason and logical reason. The comparative study is helpful for us to understand
the two masters’ ethics, politics and philosophy.
Translated from Lunlixue Yanjiu 伦理学研究 (Research in Ethics), 2006, (1): 47–52 相似文献
103.
Veronica Vasterling 《Human Studies》2007,30(2):79-95
In this essay I compare Nussbaum’s and Arendt’s approach to narrativity. The point of the comparison is to find out which
approach is more adequate for practical philosophy: the approach influenced by cognitive theory (Nussbaum) or the one influenced
by hermeneutic phenomenology (Arendt). I conclude that Nussbaum’s approach is flawed by methodological solipsism, which is
due to her application of cognitive theory.
相似文献
Veronica VasterlingEmail: |
104.
《Canadian journal of philosophy》2012,42(3-4):27-44
Many of the central theses of Hume's philosophy – his rejection of real relations, universals, abstract objects and necessary causal relations – had precedents in the later medieval nominalist tradition. Hume and his medieval predecessors developed complex semantic theories to show both how ontologies are apt to become inflated and how, if we understand carefully the processes by which meaning is generated, we can achieve greater ontological parsimony. Tracing a trajectory from those medieval traditions to Hume reveals Hume to be more radical, particularly in his rejection of abstraction and abstract ideas. Hume's denial of general, abstract ideas is consistent with his philosophical principles but fails to appreciate the more sophisticated nominalist approaches to abstraction, the result of which is a theoretically impoverished account of our capacity for generalization. 相似文献
105.
Robert N. McCauley 《Zygon》2014,49(3):728-740
Although I certainly have differences with some of my commentators, I am grateful for the time, effort, and attention that each has devoted to my book, Why Religion Is Natural and Science Is Not. They have helpfully pointed out features of my positions that need clarification and elaboration. I am also grateful to the editor of Zygon, Willem Drees, for this opportunity to undertake that task here. 相似文献
106.
David Rousseau 《Zygon》2014,49(2):476-508
Within the scientific study of spirituality there are substantial ambiguities and uncertainties about relevant concepts, terms, evidences, methods, and relationships. Different disciplinary approaches reveal or emphasize different aspects of spirituality, such as outcomes, behaviors, skills, ambitions, and beliefs. I argue that these aspects interdepend in a way that constitutes a “systems model of spirituality.” This model enables a more holistic understanding of the nature of spirituality, and suggests a new definition that disambiguates spirituality from related concepts such as religion, cultural sophistication, and prosocial behavior in animals. It also exposes important open questions about the nature of spirituality. To support the emerging scientific approach to the study of spirituality, I propose the development of a “philosophy of spirituality” that can clarify the conceptual terrain, identify important research directions, and facilitate a comprehensive and interdisciplinary investigation into the nature, validity, and implications of spirituality's conceptual and practical entailments. 相似文献
107.
古文运动以后,面对儒释道三教抗衡局面中儒学的式微,一大批秉持儒家道统担当情怀的知识分子孜孜矻矻地希求通过改构儒学以恢复儒家的正统地位。而《周易》则因其丰蕴的形上智慧和思想资源成为了这一时期儒家知识分子普遍萃心的经典。这一缓慢的儒学复兴之路直到北宋五子才初步完成。作为“理学开山”的周敦颐成功地以《周易》作为自身的学术根基,建立了理学史上第一个高度哲学化的天人之学。由于诸多原因,学界对于周敦颐易学思想的关注较多集中在《太极图》的渊源考据上,而对其易学涵具的精深义理研究则相对较少。本文以学理研究为主,在前人研究的成果上,试图对周敦颐易学的脉络做一简单梳理。 相似文献
108.
Pauli Pylkkö 《The Journal of analytical psychology》2023,68(3):515-533
Jung’s final psychoid theory of archetypes was an additional attempt to find a solution to the philosophical problem of how to relate mind and matter. In the following essay Jung’s solution is summarized by a set of 17 theses, and Jung’s philosophy will be called psychoid monism. According to psychoid monism, what ultimately and primarily is, is the psycho-physically neutral domain of instinctual experience. The origin of this view can be traced back to Post-Kantian German Idealism (Schopenhauer, Schelling, Hölderlin), and a systematization of the view requires a dialectic approach and, in particular, contradiction-tolerant dialectic logic. 相似文献
109.
James Norton 《Metaphilosophy》2023,54(1):3-16
This paper defends the usefulness of the concept of philosophical progress and the common assumption that philosophy and science aim to make the same, or a comparable, kind of progress. It does so by responding to Yafeng Shan's (2022) arguments that the wealth of research on scientific progress is not applicable or useful to philosophy, and that philosophy doesn't need a concept of progress at all. It is ultimately argued that while Shan's arguments are not successful, they reveal the way forward in developing accounts of philosophical progress. 相似文献
110.
Randall Auxier 《Metaphilosophy》2023,54(4):390-402
This is a performative piece of writing in the presence of and inspired by Richard Shusterman's Philosophy and the Art of Writing. It tries to show that the relationship between the act of writing and the formation of our human consciousness (philosophical and, more deeply, poietic) is a developing and growing process through history, and before it. The dominance of an image consciousness was slowly challenged and then replaced by a linguistic consciousness with the advent of writing, and accelerated by the invention of printing and mass literacy. Shusterman teaches us an embodied kind of philosophizing that uses the word but isn't limited by it. This paper suggests that a return to image consciousness has already occurred and that the old book consciousness is disappearing. Lessons from the book consciousness are offered. 相似文献